Está en la página 1de 8

134 Recensioni

vocabulario de los tiempos. Ciertamente en este sentido, cómo la justicia es el inicio


los Papas y los concilios no ha desentrañado del amor. Toda persona, cada persona tiene
de forma completa la profunda infraestruc- derecho a ser amada. El amor es el único
tura filosófica y teológica implicada en los modo justo de tratar a una persona. Se ter-
derechos humanos, con las definiciones y mina en esta parte con el fundamento teoló-
distinciones que la acompañan. No era su gico de los derechos en Cristo, en su ser
intención ni su misión. Esto es tarea de los ‘imago Dei’.
filósofos y teólogos. Lo que en definitiva El capítulo cuarto (pp. 217-300) es tam-
muestra esta valiosa obra es que la aporta- bién muy importante. Se sostiene que, aun-
ción principal de la tradición católica al dis- que el término de los ‘derechos’ sea relati-
curso sobre los derechos humanos se en- vamente nuevo, las ideas que entrañan
cuentra en la filosofía y teología hunden sus raíces en la gran tradición teo-
antropológicas que los fundamentan, espe- lógica y filosófica del cristianismo. Son
cialmente como se ha desarrollado en el parte integrante y esencial de la enseñanza
‘personalismo tomista’. sobre la ley natural y el derecho natural. La
El libro se divide en cinco capítulos. El quinta parte (pp. 301-320) es también la
primero (pp. 3-52) sirve para definir los de- conclusión, donde se recapitula lo visto y se
rechos, aportar matices y mostrar la posi- reafirma la necesidad de responder en la
ción de la Iglesia. La distinción entre dere- práctica, con un amor solidario, a la inquie-
chos ‘naturales’ y derechos ‘positivos’ o tante pregunta: ‘¿quién es mi prójimo?’
‘legales’ es de gran ayuda. En el segundo Un pequeño reparo es la postura más
(pp. 53-107) se defiende el concepto de bien crítica hacia el pensamiento de G. Gri-
‘derechos humanos’ o ‘derechos naturales’ sez y J. Finnis en cuanto a la ley natural y
frente a las acusaciones de su no existencia, los bienes fundamentales. Pienso que una
de su inseparabilidad del liberalismo ilumi- cuidadosa lectura de estos pensadores puede
nista y de su carácter de novedad en el pen- llevar a una diversa apreciación.
samiento de la Iglesia. El tercer capítulo es
el corazón del ensayo, donde se presenta el José María Antón, L.C.
‘personalismo tomista’ como fundamento
de los derechos humanos (pp. 108-216). Se
explica brillantemente lo que se entiende
por ‘personalismo’, ‘persona’ y ‘dignidad’.
Se distingue entre el amor concupiscentiae Rudi te Velde, Aquinas on God: The ‘Di-
y el amor benevolentiae, siendo éste último vine Science’ of the Summa Theologiae,
el único modo justo de amar a una persona Ashgate, Aldershot 2006, 192 pp.
y, por consiguiente, a cada persona, sin dis-
tinción de raza, sexo, religión, cualidades, In his Aquinas on God, Rudi te Velde,
clase social, etc. Se muestra la íntima unión philosophy professor of the University of
entre el bien de la persona –que no es indi- Tilburg (Netherlands), provides insight into
vidualismo o egoísmo– y el bien común. De the structural, methodological and system-
la dignidad de la persona surgen los dere- atic aspects of Thomas Aquinas’ approach
chos humanos, y del amor que le debemos, to God in the Summa theologiae. In the In-
nuestra obligación de respetarlos como troduction, te Velde states that the aim of his
modo de respetar a la persona, cuidando, en book is “to expound and explain Thomas’
consecuencia, de los bienes que son para analysis of the concept of God, with the
ella fundamentales, como la vida, la verdad, accent on the way in which the ‘theological’
la religión, el vivir en sociedad, el matrimo- and the ‘philosophical’ are hereby inter-
nio. Basado sobre todo en el pensamiento woven” (p. 1) and explains that Thomas’
filosófico y teológico de Juan Pablo II –in- metaphysical approach to God (as prima
cluyendo de modo principal sus escritos causa) in the Summa is integrated within a
como ‘Karol Wojtyla’– el autor muestra, comprehensive treatment of Christian faith.
Recensioni 135

Te Velde divides his book into six chap- tion in which two main shifts of perspective
ters, summarizing them as follows: Chapter occur. First, divine government, with re-
One introduces the Summa theologiae, its spect to the rational creature, requires a new
subject matter, method and composition; perspective in which the focus is on the hu-
Chapter Two is devoted to the question of man agent who is assisted in his work of
God’s existence and attends especially to freedom by God’s law and grace; second,
the first argument based on motion; Chapter God’s graceful and helping presence to
Three deals with what God is, namely mankind in his historical reality of damaged
Thomas’ understanding of God as self-sub- freedom is intensified by God becoming
sistent being; Chapter Four deals with man in Christ, in which the two agencies of
Thomas’ analysis of how God can be named God and man become united, restoring
by means of human language and the doc- from within the damaged freedom of man in
trine of analogy; Chapter Five deals with his orientation to God. The three parts of the
the notion of creation and Thomas’ meta- Summa do not appear to be organized ac-
physics of participation; Chapter Six dis- cording to the double movement of exitus
cusses “the notion of grace and the system- and reditus, but rather according to three
atic relevance in Thomas’ thought of the agents: God, Man and Christ, respectively”
difference between ‘nature’ and ‘grace’” (p. 18).
(p. 6). After clarifying what Thomas means
In Chapter One, “A Masterpiece of The- by sacra doctrina and how the special na-
ology: Aims, Method and Composition of ture of this doctrine determines the main di-
the Summa theologiae”, te Velde recalls vision of the Summa into three parts, te
that, for Thomas, thinking about what God Velde looks at how philosophy enters into
is and what God does “is intrinsically con- the project of the Summa and how the status
nected with a theological consideration of of sacred doctrine as a scientia ought to be
the moral practice of human life as directed understood. He explains the interplay be-
towards God, as well as with an inquiry in tween disciplina and doctrina and the ped-
the life and deeds of Jesus Christ, who, by agogical ordering of sacra doctrina and
his redemptive action, has opened for man that, according to Thomas, sacra doctrina is
the access to God” (p. 10). The Summa is a subaltern science: “Its conclusions are
structured accordingly: the First Part of the based on principles known by the light of a
Summa “contains the doctrine of God and superior scientia, namely the scientia of
of creation, the Second Part deals with the God and the blessed (that is, those who en-
moral practice of man whose final happi- joy the final vision of God). These princi-
ness lies in being united with God, and the ples, from which the scientia of faith pro-
Third Part deals with Christ and his sacra- ceeds, are identified by Thomas as the
ments through which the ultimate unity of articles of faith” (p. 25-26). Sacred doctrine
man and God is brought about” (p. 10). In is based on revelation and as such is distinct
light of this triadic plan, te Velde holds that from all the philosophical sciences. On the
M.-D. Chenu’s hermeneutical perspective one hand, it accepts its principles from God
of exitus-reditus is problematic, since, when through revelation and, in this sense, does
a more detailed application of exitus-reditus not depend on the philosophical sciences,
is attempted, it tends to obscure and conceal yet, on the other, “although all the scientia
some of the Summa’s methodical and com- of sacred doctrine is founded in God him-
positional peculiarities and does not appear self and as such is superior to all the philo-
to fit in with how Thomas himself accounts sophical sciences, we humans need the as-
for the divisions and transitions in the text. sistance of philosophy in order to obtain a
In contrast to Chenu’s exitus-reditus clearer understanding of its truths” (p. 28).
perspective, te Velde proposes the follow- Philosophy, te Velde concludes, “is needed
ing: “The Summa proceeds according to a due to the imperfection of the human intel-
linear movement of increasing concretiza- lect, ‘which is more easily led (manuduci-
136 Recensioni

tur) by what is known through natural rea- (Deum esse), not the existence of God him-
son to that which is above reason’ (I, q. 1, self (esse Dei)” (p. 44). Since the definition
a. 5 ad 2)” (p. 28). Te Velde ends the first of God’s essence cannot be used as the mid-
chapter with a reflection on the notion of dle term in the definition, we have to use the
“manuductio” and the status and mediatory meaning of the name “God”. Te Velde ar-
role of philosophical reason in the exposi- gues that the meaning of the name “God”
tion of the doctrine of faith: “Philosophy stems from our knowledge of God’s nature
does not prove the truth of faith, but it according to causality, excellence and remo-
shows by means of metaphysical reason tion, for we intend to signify something
that there must be a First Being and a First which transcends all things, is the principle
Cause in relation to which the statements of of all things and is removed from all things.
faith have their truth. Without reason’s With respect to the structure of the First
manuductio, by which the subject of the Way, we see that our reason needs to move
revealed doctrine of faith is given an intel- from the philosophical analysis of motion to
ligible determination, the Christian revela- the metaphysical plane of a “First Mover”,
tion cannot be understood to be what it is which is the principle of all motion in rela-
assumed to be: knowledge which is true of tion to which the whole order of secondary
God” (p. 30). movers (nature) receives its ultimate ex-
In Chapter Two, “The First Thing to planation (cf. p. 51). Not every being is
Know: Does God Exist? On the Five mobile and, therefore, the perspective of
Ways”, te Velde starts by noting that St. physics must be transcended. In this sense,
Thomas’s Five Ways have traditionally the argument of the prima via may be re-
been considered as arguments aiming at a garded as passing over from physics to
logically conclusive proof of God’s exis- metaphysics by way of resolutio: “Resolutio
tence and rational justification of theistic names the process of reason by which the
belief. In contrast to this position, te Velde composed sensible whole, which is better
proposes that, in the Summa, the question as known to us, is reduced to its simple prin-
to whether God exists is first and foremost ciples and causes, which are better known
a matter of finding an access (via) to the in- in themselves” (p. 55). Resolutio, then, is
telligibility of God. The Five Ways have a twofold: it is both a reductive process that
theological context and aim, and are a nec- occurs within the field of a certain science
essary “first step in the systematic exposi- and a process which may lead “to a change
tion of the scientia of sacred doctrine inas- in the relationship of thought to the object,
much as they provide the initial access to constitutive of a science. […] By way of
the intelligibility of the subject of this sci- resolution the particular object of physics is
entia” (p. 39). Since the arguments address resolved into the universal object of meta-
the question of how our belief that God ex- physics” (p. 55).
ists may be rationally ascertained in its ref- Chapter Three, “The Heart of the Mat-
erence to objective reality, te Velde first ter: What God Is (Not)”, deals with
clarifies the technical meaning of the ques- Thomas’ answer to the question “Quid sit
tion “An sit?” in Aquinas’ thought and then Deus?”. Due to the limits of our intellect we
discusses the problem of whether and how cannot know what God is and therefore the
God’s existence admits of a demonstration, question “quid sit” must be transformed
given the specific mediatory structure of into inquiry into “what God is not”. To an-
logical demonstration. In his exposition, te swer the question whether or not “knowing
Velde explains one of the fundamental what God is not” constitutes real knowl-
Thomistic theses: the existence of God is edge, te Velde sets out to determine the na-
not per se known by the intellect, yet may ture of the negative dimension in our
be known in a demonstration quia from the knowledge of God: “For Thomas, the way
effects: “What we come to know as a result of negation in the approach to God is
of a demonstration is ‘that God exists’ grounded in causality. The remotio points to
Recensioni 137

the fact that God must be separated from all tens), then being must be present in it ac-
things insofar as He is the cause of all cording to its full range of perfection, in-
things. The via negationis presupposes the cluding perfections such as life and intelli-
prior affirmation of God as the cause on gence and so on. Thus it appears that in
which all things depend for their being” (p. reducing all things, with respect to their be-
75). In I, q. 12, a. 12, we find St. Thomas’ ing, to the first cause, the categorical differ-
elaborated and refined version of the ences of being in the sphere of essence are,
Dionysian triplex via according to causality, so to speak, gathered together in their orig-
remotion and eminence and a summary of inal unity in and as being itself: the simple
his view of how we can arrive at knowledge being of God contains in itself the perfec-
of God. The affirmation of God as cause tion of all things (of all genera)” (p. 89).
was begun earlier in I, q. 2, where Thomas In Chapter Four, “Divine Names: On
argues for the existence of God as the first Human Discourse about God”, te Velde be-
cause (via causalitatis). In the questions of gins by drawing attention to the guiding
the Summa that follow, Thomas seeks to es- principle which states that God manifests
tablish what must necessarily belong to God himself in the world through a diversity of
as the first cause of all things. Thus, in the perfections which flow from him into the
second step, the cause is distinguished from created effects. Te Velde prefaces his treat-
the effect by way of negation (via remotio- ment of the divine names with a brief exam-
nis). Finally, we see that the cause possesses ination of the semantic triangle of res – ra-
originally and eminently all the perfections tio – nomen, of the signification of words
of the effects (via eminentiae). Thomas thus and of the triplex via, as a guideline in the
determines the “mode of being” of the First analysis of how names may be transferred
Cause of all things by means of remotion from creatures to God. Some names signify
and eminence. God in himself, some names are said
According to te Velde, the two principal metaphorically of God and some names are
features of the divine mode of being are said properly of God. The names of God are
simplicitas (q. 3) and perfectio (q. 4). These, not synonymous since they signify the same
in turn, are presupposed by all the other at- reality under different conceptual aspects.
tributes of the divine essence. Te Velde also With this understanding te Velde turns to the
holds that the attribute of simplicitas corre- topic of analogy. Names, he writes, are said
sponds to the via remotionis and that of analogously of God and creatures – neither
perfectio to the via eminentiae, arguing that in exactly the same sense nor in a wholly
the attributes of infinity (q. 7), immutability different sense, but according to some or-
(q. 9) and unity (q. 11) incorporate a synthe- dered relationship between both. To grasp
sis of the negative aspect of simplicity and this point better, te Velde brings up two
the positive aspect of perfection, but should topics in which analogy finds an applica-
be regarded as following immediately upon tion: analogy as applied to the term “being”
simplicity, since they remove limitation, and analogy as applied to a certain type of
motion and division from God. causality called the “analogical agent”
The attributes of goodness (q. 6), divine (agens analogicum).
omnipresence (q. 8), and eternity (q. 10) fol- First, ens is said analogously of the dif-
low upon those of perfection (good), infin- ferent genera of being and is said of the dif-
ity (omnipresence) and immutability (eter- ferent categories according to different re-
nity). In the final section of the chapter, te lations to substance; as well, there are
Velde looks at Thomas’ understanding of names which are transgeneric and common
God in terms of Ipsum Esse Per Se Subsis- to all things – the transcendentals. In the
tens and Thomas’ conception of being as analogy of the divine names, the trans-
universal perfection. Te Velde concludes: generic character of being is very important.
“If a reality is completely determined in The other topic, that of the analogical agent,
identity with its being (ipsum esse subsis- concerns a type of causality in which the ef-
138 Recensioni

fect falls short with respect to the perfection Analogy, te Velde points out, is often
of its cause: “In this case the effect receives taken to be part of a sort of procedure of ab-
merely a diminished and remote likeness of straction and sublimation by which finite
its cause – a likeness which cannot be re- perfections are purged of their material
duced to a specific or even generic identity, flaws and defects and then extended to their
but which is merely according to a certain ultimate limit in God. In contrast to this, te
analogy” (p. 110). Here, analogy is meant to Velde argues that: “In the case of the anal-
designate the intelligible connection be- ogy of divine predication it is the whole of
tween cause and effect and is intrinsically all categorically distinct things as such (as
connected with the notion of participation. being) which is transcended towards some-
Two characteristics of analogical pred- thing existing extra omne genus. Analogy,
ication – the indirect denomination from in this sense, should not be understood as a
something else and the aspect of transcend- sort of transcending movement going be-
ing of one genus to another – are also of yond the particular domain of experience to
fundamental importance to understanding yet another particular being of the most
the analogy of divine names: “God is sublime and perfect kind. What has to be
named indirectly from his creatures insofar transcended is the ‘physical’ way of consid-
as creatures are related to God as their ering reality in its categorical differentiation
cause. The meaning of any name said of and manifold of this and such. […] In pass-
God therefore includes a reference to the ing over from physics to metaphysics the
meaning the name had in its application to particular and differentiated sphere of
creatures. […] When a name derived from essence is reduced to its analogical unity of
creatures is applied to God, it is used out- being. It is only be considering the whole of
side the genus in which it has its proper reality as being, it is concrete differentiate
meaning. […] The name is taken from a unity, that it can be conceived in its relation-
certain genus to signify something outside ship to God as to the first and universal
that genus, according to some relationship principle of all being” (p. 117-118).
existing between them” (p. 112). God, then, In Chapter Five: “God’s Proper Action:
relates to creatures as standing outside any On the Causality of Creation”, te Velde
genus and as the principle of all genera; it places the triadic structure of the causality
is this causal connection that grounds the of creation in the forefront: God’s work of
analogous naming of God from creatures. creation “exhibits a threefold structure of
The likeness creatures have to God is ac- bringing something into existence, in an
cording to a certain analogy. This analogy, ordered way and for the sake of some good.
however, is not according to the way in The basic division between ‘producing’,
which two things are related to a third, but ‘ordering’ and ‘preserving guiding’ con-
rather according to the way one thing is re- cerns three conceptually different aspects of
lated to another. Creatures are like God and the one single act of creation” (p. 125). It is
this likeness grounds the possibility of nam- in the human manner of conceiving God’s
ing God from creatures. Likeness is always act of creation and our logical division of it
grounded in a common form and, in the that we see a reference to the manifold
case of the relationship between creatures senses of cause: “The aspect of production
and God, the common form cannot be deter- is unmistakably associated with the efficient
mined logically by way of species or by cause (causa efficens); the distinction refers
way of genus, but only by a certain analogy. to the extrinsic formal cause (causa exem-
In the case of the divine names, analogy im- plaris), and the couple preservation/gov-
plies transcending the categorical sphere of ernment is related to the final cause (causa
finite reality as such: creatures are categor- finalis)” (p. 125-126).
ically determined and contracted in their Regarding creation as producere in esse,
being; God exceeds any categorical limita- God is thought of as the efficient agent that
tion as he is identical with his being. makes something other than himself to ex-
Recensioni 139

ist. With respect to the other two aspects, essence. Thomas denies this possibility for
Thomas is guided by two principles: First, us in this life; hence, in order to argue that
every agent acts through a form (omne all things proceed from God as from their
agens agit secundum formam) and second, (efficient) cause, we must start from the in-
every agent acts for the sake of an end direct and negative understanding of God
(omne agens agit propter finem). The form on the basis of his effects: “The way God
according to which God acts is nothing must be understood by us as the first cause
other than the one divine essence as con- of all things is expressed by the formula
ceived under many different aspects, each ‘self-subsistent being’. […] Thomas’ task
of which forms the idea of a particular crea- will now consist in showing how the truth
ture. The aspect of distinctio, which implies that every being is caused by God can be
a multitude of diverse and unequal crea- ‘deduced’ from this intelligible determina-
tures, is also associated with God’s sapien- tion of the divine essence” (p. 129).
tia, for divine wisdom contains the ideas of Although the argument of creation ap-
all things in itself. The third aspect of con- pears at first to be circular, it is in no way a
servatio/gubernatio refers to God as the fi- vicious circle since it proceeds from an in-
nal cause of all creatures. God leads things direct and negative understanding of God
towards their final goal and perfection, and not from an a priori definition of God.
“which is to become like (assimilatio) the Just as our knowledge of God is indirect, so
divine goodness according to the possibili- is our knowledge of creation. After this
ties of each creature’s proper nature” (p. premise, te Velde divides the argument for
128). The end to which God’s gubernatio is creation in I, q. 44, a. 1 into five steps: first,
directed is nothing other than the essential the argument states the need of a reduction:
goodness which is God himself. “The as- “Whatever is found in anything by partici-
similatio to God’s goodness happens in two pation must be caused in it by that to which
ways: first insofar as a creature is good in it- it belongs essentially; second, we are re-
self; second insofar as a creature may cause minded that God is “self-sufficient being”
something else to be good” (p. 128). God’s and must necessarily be one; third, the iden-
gubernatio corresponds to these two ways tity of being itself in God is negated with re-
of assimilatio and has a twofold effect: “it spect to everything that is not God: “All be-
preserves things in the good they have (con- ings other than God are not their own being,
servatio in bono), and it moves things to- but are beings by participation”; fourth,
wards the good (motio ad bonum)” (p. 128). creatures are seen to be diversified accord-
After establishing this triadic structure, ing to the diverse participations in being,
te Velde then looks at the argument for cre- from which results the different degrees of
ation as found in I, q. 44, which considers being; finally, each creature is an ens “in a
the whole of reality in the light of their first different way according to how it differently
cause according to the pattern of the four relates to the esse it has received from the
types of causality (efficient, material, for- First Being” (p. 131-132). After considering
mal, final). With respect to each of these, the argument found in article one, te Velde
God is shown to be the first principle of all considers article two, in which Thomas dis-
things: “God brings all things into exis- tinguishes three phases in the development
tence, including their matter, and according of the philosophical investigation of being.
to an exemplary form which is not external The third phase moves from a particular
to God, and in view of an end which is consideration of being as nature to the uni-
nothing other than God’s goodness” (p. versal consideration of being as being and
129). The proposition that “every being is the causality of creation. In this step, the
created by God” would not be a problem if movement of resolutio reaches its conclu-
we were able to see the essence of God— sion: being is conceived as not depending
for we would immediately grasp the truth on matter and, thus, must be created by the
that all things flow from God’s creative universal cause of things. Our author con-
140 Recensioni

cludes the chapter looking at creation as ments and arguments from the First Part of
participation – participation as it applies to the Summa, he limits himself rather to ex-
the composition of the principles of essence plaining Thomas’ metaphysics as it is inte-
and esse in creatures and insofar as it under- grated within the sacra doctrina based on
lines the total dependency of the creature on divine revelation. This focus has both its ad-
the universal source of being. vantages and drawbacks. Advantageous is
In Chapter Six, “A God of Grace: On the attention given to the Summa’s structure
Human Freedom and Divine Grace”, te and method. Understanding these better
Velde enters into themes that pertain more constitutes te Velde’s primary goal. Such at-
properly to Sacred Theology. Te Velde jus- tention allows us to get into the way
tifies the inclusion of the chapter arguing Thomas thinks and brings us beyond com-
that grace is an essential feature of Thomas’ mentaries that sometimes tend to obscure
metaphysical understanding of God. Grace what Thomas states succinctly and clearly.
presupposes nature and perfects nature. In this sense, te Velde’s book contributes
Man has a connatural end proportioned to greatly to the effort of those who would at-
his nature and a supernatural end which ex- tempt to construct a philosophical theology
ceeds the faculty of his nature. This obser- by pulling elements and arguments from
vation leads te Velde to the theme of the the Summa.
two types of human happiness according to Te Velde’s explanations of resolutio as
the duality of nature and grace. He holds a method within a science and as a way of
that it is from the perspective of the natural passing from physics to metaphysics and
desire for truth that philosophical happiness his explanation of the role of the middle
– the earthly contemplation of the divine term in the demonstration of God’s exis-
cause as knowable from the likeness of cre- tence, the triplex via in our knowledge of
ation – and supernatural happiness – the vi- what God is (not), the analogy of divine
sion of God’s essence – are comparable to names in connection with God as extra
each other in terms of imperfect and per- omne genus and principle of certain genera
fect. Since the vision of God’s essence is and the triadic structure of the treatise on
beyond the power of any created (intellec- creation are very welcome and insightful
tual) nature, it can only become “connat- contributions. One is left with the impres-
ural” to a human person if his nature is sion that there is a great deal of scholarship
perfected to participate in the divine nature. and remarkable breadth of understanding
For this reason, the effect of God’s grace in behind each chapter.
the human soul is described in terms of re- As for the possible drawbacks to te
creation and re-generation (cf. I, q. 110, a. Velde’s choice in topics and approach, I
4). Grace, then, is defined as a certain par- was surprised not find a chapter dedicated
ticipation of the divine nature on the part of to God’s intellect and will, themes which
the rational creature. By “communicating a are found in the Summa and integral to its
likeness of his nature, God creates in the treatise on God. An open question remains
human soul the conditions under which a that of how the via remotionis and via em-
mutual relationship of friendship and love inentiae are applied in the argumentation
between man and God becomes possible” for the existence and object of God’s intel-
(p. 165). lect and will.
In this brief summary, I hope to have Secondly, te Velde’s treatment of dis-
conveyed both the depth and clarity of te tinctio and conservatio/gubernatio could
Velde’s exposition. The title of the Ashgate have been more extensive. In particular,
series of studies is actually a little mislead- one notes the absence of a more in-depth
ing as it makes one naturally expect a book explanation of the role of the divine ideas in
on Aquinas’ philosophical theology. While terms of exemplary causality and the role of
te Velde acknowledges that one can develop final causality in divine governance. As
such a philosophical theology using ele- well, no mention is made of the problems
Recensioni 141

surrounding passive creation as a relation in Finally, in Chapter Five, our author in-
the creature. corporates his understanding of the real dis-
Thirdly, te Velde does not explicitly ad- tinction and the notion of participation from
dress what the Summa presupposes and his earlier work, Participation and Sub-
while he recognizes that there are two the- stantiality (E.J. Brill, 1995). His point about
ologies (philosophical theology as meta- esse being limited “to” a determinate
physics and Sacred Theology), this does essence and not “by” an essence is insight-
not appear to be a driving principle in his ful, yet may in the end be a semantic dis-
exposition and interpretation of the meta- tinction that refers to the same role of the
physics integrated in the theology proper to essence when it is considered as a constitu-
the Summa theologiae. Some of his argu- tive principle of created being. In the end,
ments could be bolstered by referring to however – and I think the reader will agree
the fact that metaphysics as philosophical – these points do not take away significantly
theology does not consider God as its genus from the benefit one receives from reading
subiectum, but rather as the cause of its and reflecting on te Velde’s fine work.
genus subiectum: ens in quantum est ens.
Fourthly, if the reader is not aware that Jason A. Mitchell, L.C.
te Velde’s affirmations are in large part lim-
ited to the Summa theologiae, some affirma-
tions could easily be taken out of context
and misunderstood. Take, for example, the
affirmation found in Chapter Two: “The
Five Ways do not constitute a sort of natural
theology apart from and preceding the the-
ological exposition of faith” (p. 47). This, I
would argue, is true insofar as the Five
Ways form part of the Summa theologiae.
However, if we take into account the devel-
opment of the different arguments for the
existence of God in Thomas’ thought and
their role in other works such as the Summa
contra Gentiles, the theological contextual-
ization does not appear to be essential to the
Five Ways and does not hinder in any way
their use in “natural theology”.
Also, in Chapter Two, te Velde could
have addressed the question about the struc-
ture of the Five Ways taken together and
why there are five ways instead of just one.
I suggest that the triadic structure of effi-
cient, exemplary and final causality is once
again applicable. In Chapter Three, te
Velde’s position on the role of the via remo-
tionis and via eminentiae could be modified
to account for the fact that “perfection”
could also be seen as a “negation of lack”
(cf. In V Metaph., lect. 18, n. 1040) and,
therefore, could be said to fall within the via
remotionis along with the other four major
divine attributes.

También podría gustarte