Está en la página 1de 3

Zootaxa 2765: 5860 (2011) www.mapress.

com / zootaxa/ Copyright 2011 Magnolia Press

ISSN 1175-5326 (print edition)

Correspondence

ZOOTAXA
ISSN 1175-5334 (online edition)

Philosophically speaking, how many species concepts are there?


JOHN S. WILKINS
Department of Philosophy, University of Sydney, NSW 2006, Australia. E-mail: john@wilkins.id.au

Its an old question in biology: what is a species? Many different answers have been given over the years, and there are indefinitely many definitions in the literature. Adding to R. L. Maydens list of 22 definitions (Mayden, 1997) , I counted 26 in play since the Modern Synthesis (2009a), and a new one, which I call the polyphasic concept (basically a consilience of many lines of morphological, ecological, genetic, and physiological evidence), has been implicitly extended from bacterial and other microbial contexts to macrobial species, although the terminology has not yet been transplanted (Colwell, 1970; Vandamme et al., 1996). However, on another count there are seven basic species concepts: agamospecies (asexuals), biospecies (reproductively isolated sexual species), ecospecies (ecological niche occupiers), evolutionary species (evolving lineages), genetic species (common gene pool), morphospecies (species defined by their form, or phenotypes), and taxonomic species (whatever a taxonomist calls a species). Notice that some of these seven basic concepts are not concepts of what species are, that is, what makes them species, but instead are concepts based on how we identify species: by morphology, or the practices of taxonomists. Others are roughly equivalent. A gene pool is defined as a population of genomes that can be exchanged, and so a genetic species is basically a reproductive species. Evolutionary species are not what species are so much as what happens when some processes (such as ecological adaptation or reproductive isolation) make them species that persist over a long time. One common concept of species, the so-called phylogenetic species concept, is likewise a mix either of morphospecies, biospecies or evospecies or all of them (Wilkins, 2009b). The polyphasic concept is also based upon a method for identifying species through many kinds of evidence. Agamospecies are species that lack some property: sex. An agamospecies is a not-biospecies species (although some, like G. G. Simpson and Ernst Mayr, simply denied they were species, which is a problem given that sex is a relatively rare property in the universal tree of life; it means most biological taxa do not come in species). So what makes an agamospecies a species? It cant be reproductive isolation, for obvious reasons, so it must be the only thing that we have left on the list: ecological niche adaptation (Wilkins, 2007). It could be chance, but if grouping happens by chance it is unlikely to be maintained by chance. In the absence of sex, therefore, we need ecological niche adaptation to keep the cluster from just randomly evaporating. Of course, few if any species are purely asexual in the sense that they dont ever exchange genes; microbes have several mechanisms to do this even if they lack genders or mating types and fail to reproduce by any other means than division. Some genetic material can be exchanged through viral insertion, through DNA reuptake in the medium after a cell has lysed, or by deliberate insertion of small rings of DNA, plasmids, through pili. Horizontal or lateral genetic transfer is probably as old as life itself. While this might introduce some genetic variation into a population, it is selection for a local fitness peak that makes the asexual genome not stray too far from the wild type. As sex becomes more frequent, rising from near zero recombination per generation up to the maximum of 50% exchanged for obligately sexual organisms, another factor comes into play. Increasingly, the compatibility of genomes, reproductive processes at the cellular, organ, and physiological level become important. In organisms with behavioral signaling (that is, with nervous systems and sensory organs), reproductive behaviours like calls and movements become important. Sex acts to ensure that the organisms that can interbreed tend to be those whose genome and anatomy are consistent enough. I call this reproductive reach (2003; 2007): the more closely two organisms are related, the more likely they are within each others reach as potential mates, and so the species is maintained by reproductive compatibility, and of course some ecological adaptation. This is very similar to a definition of species by the geneticist Alan Templeton (1989), who said that species were the most inclusive population of individuals having the potential for phenotypic cohesion through intrinsic cohesion mechanisms, that defines a species as the most inclusive group of organisms having the potential for genetic and/or demographic exchangeability. [My emphasis.] Genetic exchangeability here means the ability to act in the same manner in reproduction any two members of the species are (more or less) interchangeable. Demographic exchangeability means that any two members of the species behave the

58

Accepted by M. Ebach: 8 Jan. 2011; published: 15 Feb. 2011

same, ecologically, behaviorally and so forth, and are interchangeable (more or less). With these two causes of being a species, we can now narrow down the number of concepts to two: ecospecies or biospecies. Theres a philosophical matter to clear up. These causal explanations are just that: explanations. They are not the concept of species. There was a concept of species before we had any clear idea of what they might be. We identified species in the 16th century that are still regarded as species, and there wasnt the slightest hint of an explanation in the air at the time. There is also a difference between the use of species definitions as aids to discovery, and explanation. A number of species conceptions have been formulated as operational aids to identifying a new species. Some of these are genetic or molecular (Birky, Adams, Gemmel, & Perry, 2010; Caron, Countway, & Brown, 2004; Hanage, Fraser, & Spratt, 2005; Sites & Marshall, 2003; Staley, 2006), and some are morphological (e.g., John & Maggs, 1997; Purvis, 1997), but many conceptions have attached to them species delimitation techniques or protocols (de Queiroz, 2007; DeSalle, Egan, & Siddall, 2005; Knowles & Carstens, 2007; Raxworthy, Ingram, Rabibisoa, & Pearson, 2007; Tobias et al., 2010). Mostly these are conventions of the subdiscipline or field rather than natural classifications. Many of them are phenetic or phylogenetic conceptions or both (Beltran et al., 2002; Mallet, 1995; Templeton, 1989; Templeton, Maskas, & Cruzan, 2000). Theory-based concepts presume the universal applicability of that theory outside the groups on which it was formulated (e.g., Wu, 2001a; 2001b). Discovery techniques that are based upon explanatory concepts are hostage to empirical fortune. And its an old concept, too, although the first simply biological definition of species (a Latin word that means form or appearance) waited until 1686 when John Ray defined it. Rays definition was based on a simple observation: progeny resemble their parents. Species are those groups of organisms that resemble their parents. Versions of it go back to the Greeks. According to this, there is some power, a generative capacity, to make progeny resemble parents, and it seems to rely upon seeds. I call this the generative conception of species, and it was not only the default view before Darwin, but Darwin himself held it, as do nearly all modern biologists. It is what it is that the explanations explain. So technically there is only one species concept, of which all the others, the 2 or 7 or 27, are conceptions. The idea that there is one generic category into which there are put many concepts is a mistake made by Ernst Mayr (1963). In ordinary philosophical usage, it is the concept that is the category, and the definitions define, in various ways, that concept. Another mistake often made by biologists is to think that if there is a concept/category, there has to be a specified rank or level at which all species arise (Baum, 2009). This seems to rely on the idea that because Linnaeus took Rays concept of species and made it the lowest rank in his classification scheme, there has to be something that all and only species have as properties, and it has caused no end of confusion. That species all exist does not imply that all species have some essential property (any more than because we can usually identify what an organism is implies there is something that all and only organisms share). This philosophical error is called essentialism, and it is a supreme irony that Mayr, the opponent of essentialism about individual species, was held in thrall to essentialism about taxonomic concepts. Some people think that there are no species. Moreover, they wrongly think this view is a consequence of evolution and that Darwin himself denied there were any. Now what Darwin thought 150 years ago is of no real consequence to modern biology, but he didnt think species were unreal constructs; he thought there was no single set of properties species had to have. He was not a taxonomic essentialist. But neither is it the case that species are unreal because they shade into each other. In modern philosophy, there is an ongoing debate over whether one can have vague and fuzzy sets or kinds, but for science we need only a little logic and metaphysics: If we can identify mountains, rivers, and organisms, we can identify species, and they will tend to have a family resemblance (Wittgenstein, 1968). What is a species among primates will tend to be like species in all other close relatives. What is a species among lizards will (usually) be like what a species is in close relatives (some lizards are parthenogens; and have no males, where their nearest relatives are sexual, but in that case they are like their sexual cousins ecologically and morphologically; see Wilkins, 2003). But some think that species do not exist except in the minds of biologists and their public (Hey, 2001a; 2001b; Pleijel, 1999; Vrana & Wheeler, 1992). So for them, zero. Our final score is: 2627, 7, 2, 1 or 0. My solution is this: There is one species concept. There are two explanations of why real species are species (see my microbial paper, 2007): ecological adaptation and reproductive reach. There are seven distinct definitions of species, and 27 current variations and mixtures. And there are n+1 definitions of species in a room of n biologists.

Bibliography
Baum, D.A. (2009) Species as Ranked Taxa. Systematic Biology, 58, 7486. Beltran, M., Jiggins, C.D., Bull, V., Linares, M., Mallet, J., McMillan, W.O. & Bermingham, E. (2002) Phylogenetic discordance at the species boundary: comparative gene genealogies among rapidly radiating heliconius butterflies.

HOW MANY SPECIES CONCEPTS ARE THERE?

Zootaxa 2765 2011 Magnolia Press

59

Molecular Biology and Evolution, 19, 21762190. Birky, C. W., Jr., Adams, J., Gemmel, M. & Perry, J. (2010) Using Population Genetic Theory and DNA Sequences for Species Detection and Identification in Asexual Organisms. PLoS ONE, 5, e10609. Caron, D.A., Countway, P.D. & Brown, M.V. (2004) The growing contributions of molecular biology and immunology to protistan ecology: molecular signatures as ecological tools. The Journal of Eukaryotic Microbiology, 51, 3848. Colwell, R.R. (1970) Polyphasic taxonomy of bacteria. Culture collections of microorganisms, 421436. de Queiroz, K. (2007) Species Concepts and Species Delimitation. Systematic Biology, 56, 879886. DeSalle, R., Egan, M.G. & Siddall, M. (2005) The unholy trinity: taxonomy, species delimitation and DNA barcoding. Philosophical Transactions: Biological Sciences, 360, 19051916. Hanage, W.P., Fraser, C. & Spratt, B.G. (2005) Fuzzy species among recombinogenic bacteria. BMC Biology, 3. Hey, J. (2001a) Genes, concepts and species: the evolutionary and cognitive causes of the species problem. New York: Oxford University Press. Hey, J. (2001b) The mind of the species problem. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 16, 326329. John, D.M. & Maggs, C.A. (1997) Species problems in eukaryotic algae: a modern perspective. In: M. F. Claridge, H. A. Dawah & M. R. Wilson (Eds), Species: the units of biodiversity. Chapman and Hall, London, pp. 83107. Knowles, L.L. & Carstens, B.C. (2007) Delimiting Species without Monophyletic Gene Trees. Systematic Biology, 56, 887 895. Mallet, J. (1995) The species definition for the modern synthesis. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 10, 294299. Mayden, R.L. (1997) A hierarchy of species concepts: the denoument in the saga of the species problem. In Species: The units of diversity, edited by M. F. Claridge, H. A. Dawah and M. R. Wilson. London: Chapman and Hall: 381423. Mayr, E. (1963) Animal species and evolution. Cambridge MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Pleijel, F. (1999) Phylogenetic taxonomy, a farewell to species, and a revision of Heteropodarke (Hesionidae, Polychaeta, Annelida). Systematic Biology, 48, 755789. Purvis, O.W. (1997) The species concept in lichens. In: M. F. Claridge, H. A. Dawah & M. R. Wilson (Eds), Species: the units of biodiversity. Chapman and Hall, London, pp. 109134. Raxworthy, C.J., Ingram, C.M., Rabibisoa, N. & Pearson, R.G. (2007) Applications of Ecological Niche Modeling for Species Delimitation: A Review and Empirical Evaluation Using Day Geckos (Phelsuma) from Madagascar. Systematic Biology, 56, 907923. Sites, J.W. & Marshall, J.C. (2003) Delimiting species: a Renaissance issue in systematic biology. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 18, 462470. Staley, J.T. (2006) The bacterial species dilemma and the genomicphylogenetic species concept. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 361, 18991909. Templeton, A.R. (1989) The meaning of species and speciation: A genetic perspective. In: D. Otte & J. Endler (Eds), Speciation and its consequences. Sinauer, Sunderland, MA, pp. 327. Templeton, A.R., Maskas, S.D. & Cruzan, M.B. (2000) Gene trees: a powerful tool for exploring the evolutionary biology of species and speciation. Plant Species Biology, 15, 211222. Tobias, J.A., Seddon, N., Spottiswoode, C.N., Pilgrim, J.D., Fishpool, L.D.C. & Collar, N.J. (2010) Quantitative criteria for species delimitation. Ibis, 152, 724746. Vandamme, P., Pot, B., Gillis, M., de Vos, P., Kersters, K. & Swings, J. (1996) Polyphasic taxonomy, a consensus approach to bacterial systematics. Microbiology Reviews, 60, 407438. Vrana, P. & Wheeler, W. (1992) Individual organisms as terminal entities: Laying the species problem to rest. Cladistics, 8, 67 72. Wilkins, J.S. (2003) How to be a chaste species pluralist-realist: The origins of species modes and the Synapomorphic Species Concept. Biology and Philosophy, 18, 621638. Wilkins, J.S. (2007) The Concept and Causes of Microbial Species. Studies in History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 28, 389408. Wilkins, J.S. (2009a) Defining species: a sourcebook from antiquity to today. New York: Peter Lang. Wilkins, J.S. (2009b) Species: a history of the idea. Berkeley: University of California Press. Wittgenstein, L. (1968) Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans. Repr. of [3rd ed.] English text, with index. ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Wu, C.-I. (2001a) Genes and speciation. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 14, 889891. Wu, C.-I. (2001b) The genic view of the process of speciation. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 14, 851865.

60

Zootaxa 2765 2011 Magnolia Press

WILKINS

También podría gustarte