Está en la página 1de 4

of being progressive, subversive,” “It’s about keeping things

as they are as opposed to changing things?”


Thordis Arrhenius
The Cult of Age in Mass-Society:
Alois Riegl’s Theory of Conservation
AAV
V: Well it is not possible to keep things as they are because
the subject changes. Even if you were able to place the build-
ing in a glass jar and preserve it perfectly, a hundred years
from now the viewer will be approaching it with a set of very
different issues, and in his or her mind it will be a very differ- In “The Modern Cult of Monuments: Its Character and Its
ent object. This of course is based on my personal opinion Origin,” the Austrian art historian Alois Riegl made an unprece-
that objects are not only physical facts but, more importantly dented attempt to speculate on the popularization of heritage
for me, materializations of ideas, inherently subjective things. in Western culture.1 His 1903 essay remains fascinating as it
predicts the imminent emergence of a ubiquitous admiration
JJO
OPP: That fluid sense of buildings as objects of subjective for the old, while putting forward an intriguing proposal for
processes comes through strongly in this work. It calls upon how this “cult” of the old would affect the notion of the “mon-
people to take an active part in that process of interpretation. ument.” Intriguingly, Riegl identified age as the clue to the
That’s what’s interesting for me about your project: it picks up extension of heritage into mass-culture. Age, signified through
on histories both personal and national, and serves to amplify disintegration, manifested itself immediately to the beholder;
them, and that’s really quite amazing. Do you feel that it’s the no scientific or art historical knowledge was needed to appre-
responsibility of the artist or preservationist to help people ciate its visual qualities.2 Riegl saw this visual directness as
confront and develop their history? the future potential of age in a mass-society directed by
moods and feelings, what he called Stimmung, rather than
AAV
V: For me as an artist, yes, although there are so many rational thinking. A review of Riegl’s groundbreaking essay and
artists in the world and as many different approaches. It its speculations about the monument highlights contradictions
would be wrong to start assigning responsibilities – I always and complexities that still mark the discourse and practice of
think that this has to be a very personal choice. conservation today.
Riegl begins with a definition: “A monument,” he writes,
“in its oldest and most original sense is a human creation,
erected for a specific purpose of keeping single human deeds
or events alive in the minds of future generations.”3 He points
out that the erection and care of such “intentional” commem-
orative monuments can be traced back to the beginning of
human culture. And yet, Riegl suggests, these monuments are
no longer central: “When we talk about the modern cult and
preservation of monuments, we are thinking not about ‘inten-
tional’ monuments, but about monuments of art and history.”4
Riegl notes that even this definition of the monument is too
reductive and does not acknowledge that the concept of an
absolute inviolable canon of art has given way to a modern
relative “art-value.”5 Instead, Riegl suggests an important dis-
tinction between “intentional” and “unintentional” monu-
ments.
Riegl sees the development of heritage as a phenomenon
closely connected to a perception of history as a movement
trapped in the knowledge that what has been can never be
again: “Everything that has been and is no longer we call his-
torical.”6 Through this notion of the irreplaceability of every
Future Anterior
Volume 1 Number 1 event – of the mortality of culture itself – modern man attends
Spring 2004 to artifacts left from a bygone era. These cult objects consist-
73 74
ed largely of “unintentional” monuments. Unintentional in so tion of the West, whose origin Riegl traces back to the Italian
far as they were not erected with the purpose of commemorat- Renaissance.9
ing any specific event or person, but still monuments in their Riegl notes that we define the value of the unintentional
irreplaceable value for modern man. With his concept of the monument through a process of highly visually orientated
unintentional monument Riegl makes a brutal expansion in analysis, by which the onlooker constructs the monument.
the definition of a monument: “Any artifact, regardless of its Riegl abandons the classification of the monuments them-
original significance and purpose, can be considered a monu- selves, instead identifying and distinguishing between values
ment as long as it reveals the passage of a considerable peri- applied to them – values almost exclusively based on the visu-
od of time.”7 al effect of the monument upon the beholder.
It is necessary, however, to complicate the notion of age After summarizing the historical evolution from the cult of
in order to grasp the shift from the cult of the “intentional” the intentional monument to the modern cult of unintentional
monument to the cult of the “unintentional,” which, Riegl monuments, Riegl continues by classifying and identifying the
argues, characterizes Western history from the Renaissance. different values attributed to the monument. In doing so, he
Age is a complex concept; it talks both of identification and speculates how these values determine the conservation of
distance. An intentional monument erected to commemorate a the monument. Should the monument be reconstructed to
human deed or event always has the purpose of overcoming regain its completeness and coherence of form or should it be
distance to refuse the passage of time. With its physical pres- allowed to disintegrate, to return to nature? Riegl answers this
ence, the unintentional monument aims to create a lapse in question by insisting that the answer depends on which value
time that renders the past present and establishes a transpar- the monument in question has for the beholder. He demon-
ent connection to the event or the person that the monument strates, however, that these values often conflict and demand
commemorates. The intentional monument’s primary function, different kinds of conservation strategies for the same object.
according to Riegl, is to keep memory alive; to arrest the soft Riegl distinguishes three forms of “memory-value” affect-
forgetfulness of history. For the intentional monument, age is ing the care of the monument: “intentional commemorative-
always an obstacle. Indeed the intentional monument is value” (gewollte Erinnerungswert ), “historical-value” (his-
dependent on an ageless appearance to maintain its function torische Wert ) and “age-value” (Alteswert). The first, inten-
as a memorial; any signs of decay would suggest a diminish- tional commemorative-value, only refers to the class of inten-
ing interest in the subject whose presence in memory it gov- tional monuments; the latter two relate to the class of unin-
erns. tentional monuments and are therefore part of the “modern
Riegl’s concept of the unintentional monument on the cult of monuments.” As the scope of memory-value widens the
other hand suggests a radically different logic. Where inten- different classes of monuments become contained within each
tional monuments always suppress loss through the articula- other. The class of intentional monuments includes only those
tion of triumph or martyrdom, the unintentional monuments works recalling a specific moment from the past. The monu-
leave loss at the center. Not deliberately built as monuments, ments to which a historical-value is designated still refer to a
they are found in the inflated realm of heritage as “historical specific moment in history, but are unintentional in that the
objects” that reject a transparent presence in preference for an choice of monuments is left to our subjective preference. A
obscured and distant past. Riegl underlines that both the monument that was originally only an intentional monument
intentional and the unintentional monument are characterized can therefore be incorporated into this class if it is defined as
by a commemorative value. While the value of the intentional having historical worth. The class of monuments relating to
monument is always conditioned by its makers – the monu- age-value is even more expansive in its scope. Riegl radically
ment is cared for as long as the person or event it commemo- suggests that any artifact, regardless of its original signifi-
rates is still remembered – the value of the unintentional mon- cance and purpose, could gain an age-value defining it as a
ument is relative and, as Riegl points out, left to us to define: monument, as long as it revealed to the onlooker that a con-
“When we call such works of art ‘monuments’ it is a subjective siderable period of time had passed since it was new.10
rather than an objective designation.”8 This observation is crit- The three forms of memory-value, Riegl’s Erinnerungswert,
ical, as it denotes an important distinction between the inten- suggested different strategies of restoration. To maintain an
tional and the unintentional monument. While the intentional intentional commemorative-value the monument must simply
monument appears as a trans-historical and almost ubiquitous be maintained in a pristine state. Historical-value demanded a
phenomenon, the unintentional monument is a datable inven- similar negation of age, albeit on different grounds – the mon-
75 76
ument must define a precise moment in history. In this case, conflict with historical-value, even if these values are generat-
the task of restoration is to restore the building to its “origi- ed from different positions – the first in relation to the pres-
nal” state, a requirement which risks jeopardizing the monu- ent-day value, the other from the memory-value of the monu-
ment’s validity as an authentic historical document. We can ment. The identification of a historical-value in the monument
see here that the complication of conservation emerged with often results in the reconstruction of the object as new, with a
the notion of historical-value that, in its own attention to completeness and integrity that could satisfy an art-value.
authenticity, would predicate the rise of age-value that, in Age-value, on the other hand, conflicts strongly with art-
turn, would challenge the practice of restoration directed by value. It is aging, the process of dissolution into the general
historical value. To possess an age-value the monument must that generated age-value and anything, independent of any
“truthfully” display the changes and evolutions it had under- previous aesthetic properties, could gain it. Indeed, a monu-
gone since its construction. Here, Riegl declares restoration as ment appreciated for its age-value was nothing more than a
fundamentally problematic, reducing it to preventative meas- catalyst that triggers in the beholder a sense of the life cycle.
ures to protect objects from the corrosive forces of nature or As a result, age-value is not inviolably connected to the
modernization. object. As Riegl dramatically expresses: “the object has shrunk
According to Riegl’s prophecy, age-value is the most mod- to a necessary evil”. Conversely, art-value is closely bound to
ern value and the one that would guide the conservation of the object. To satisfy both art-value and age-value in the same
the monument in the future.11 He emphasizes, however, that object is unfeasible: “where the monument’s conception,
the all-embracing value of age had yet to come, and that the shape, and color satisfy our modern ‘Kunstwollen,’ it follows
battle in conservation he experienced in 19th century Vienna that this value should not be allowed to diminish in signifi-
was often waged between historical-value and age-value. cance in order to conform to the expectations of age-value”.15
Through his careful classification and naming of different The strongest opposition to age-value, however, is what
values, Riegl shows not only how different memory-values Riegl terms newness-value (Neuheitswert ). Riegl intriguingly
conflict and demand different strategies of conservation, but and acutely places newness-value as a subclass to art-value.
also how the memory-values themselves are often antithetical He proposes that the new always has an art-value and sug-
to what he termed as present-day-values (Gegenwartswerte ). gests that the new has a specific power in modern society.
Riegl acknowledges that the monument fulfilled other Anyone can appreciate the integrity and purity of the new, and
purposes relating not only to commemoration, but also to use no education is needed to appreciate its smooth and even
and aesthetic enjoyment. He notes that these present-day val- surfaces, Riegl argues, anticipating Siegfried Giedion’s studies
ues are not part of the modern cult of monuments as they of the streamlined in 1950s American Modernism.16 In its
deny the memorial function of the monument; yet they directness, the new is a force in the same way as age in a
impacts the conservation of the monument, so their proper mass-society. Yet, the masses’ love for the new constitutes the
identification is crucial. He classifies these present-day values largest hindrance to a general recognition of age-value: “The
into two main groups: use-value and art-value. The first group masses have always enjoyed new things ... what is rooted in
refers to the practical functional performance of the object, thousands of years of perception – namely the priority of
the second to its aesthetic value for the beholder.12 The use- youth over age – cannot be eliminated in a few decades.”17
value of a monument tends to stand in conflict with the monu- The dichotomy between the attraction of the shiny new
ment’s commemorative-value – both the historical and the and the emotion for aged structures is central to Riegl’s argu-
more modern age-value.13 While age-value emerges out of the ment in “The Modern Cult of Monuments.” For Riegl, writing
gradual dissolution of form and color over time, use-value on the brink of Modernism, the attraction of the new was
requires the maintenance of the object. The inherent conflict stronger than that of the old. A century later, the situation
between these two values is evident, and informs the way appears somewhat reversed; the comfort of the old and famil-
monumental conservation is viewed. iar dominates popular discourse, perhaps most specifically in
Riegl’s notion of art-value is more complex and related to the realm of housing and urbanism, whose rhetoric almost
his concept of “Kunstwollen,” the idea of a relative and always refers to the past. Riegl’s prophecy that the force of the
changing notion of art specific to every historical period. Riegl old would conquer the masses seems to have been fulfilled.
claims that to possess art-value it was necessary that the Riegl, however, saw the power of age as a potential for
object is a discrete entity, revealing no decay of shape and the new: the cult of the old would free the new from its histor-
color.14 In Riegl’s schema, art-value does not necessarily ical burden. With truly Modernistic ambition, Riegl wanted to
77 78
break with the historicism of the 19th century.18 The new, he mary function is to provoke memories (Erinnerungen ). Riegl’s
argues, had to gain its quality specifically by differentiating notion of the unintentional monument and his identification of
itself from the old: “the truly modern work must, in its concept the modern age-value suggest that the memory function of the
and detail, recall earlier work as little as possible.”19 Riegl’s monument, as well as the very monument itself, will eventual-
age-value places the monument firmly in the realm of the old, ly become redundant. The intentional monument’s logic of
where it remains isolated from the functionality and use of the duration, expressed in its hard and durable surfaces, had gov-
everyday. The old is not to be directly reused, but only to erned the memory of its commissioner. Riegl’s record of the
return to the present in the form of its otherness – as the cult history of conservation reveals on the other hand how the
of the old. The new, conversely, defines its newness by its very monument has gradually been transformed from an object
coherence with the present and its oneness with the time. that originally communicated permanence, to an object that
“The Modern Cult of Monuments” displays the past and was about fragility and loss, removed from the present for rea-
current task of conservation in its full complexity. Riegl’s focus sons of history and sentiment.
on the cult of the monument rather than on the monuments
themselves is timeless as a deeply original contribution to the
Thordis Arrhenius is an architect and researcher. She recently concluded her Ph.D.
study of the phenomena of conservation and the role of its
thesis “The Fragile Monument; on Modernity and Conservation” at the School of
objects in a secularized and Capitalist society. Inevitably, some Architecture, KTH, in Stockholm where she also co-ordinates and teaches theory
aspects of Riegl’s analysis are bounded by his time and con- and design in the diploma year. Thordis studied at the School of Architecture in
Stockholm, the Royal Academy School of Architecture in Copenhagen, and the
text. His identification of three memory-values based on inten- Architectural Association Graduate School of Architecture in London from which
tion, history and age suggest a historical determinism imbued she holds an MA in History and Theory. She has published widely on architecture
(AA files, MAMA, Bang, Index Art Magazine and Nordic Journal of Architectural
with a Utopian desire. Riegl invested the cult of the old with Research).
altruistic dimensions that would supersede the egoistic
1
Riegl, Alois. “Der moderne Denkmalkultus. SeinWesen und seine Entstehung”.
desires of the individual and the nation. In his schema, the (Vienna: 1903), reprinted in George Dehio, A. Riegl, Konservieren, nicht restauri-
historical process evolved from the cult of the intentional eren: Streitschriften zur Denkmalphlege um 1900 (Braunschweig-Wiesbaden: Friedr.
Vieweg & Sohn, 1988). English translation: “The Modern Cult of Monuments: Its
monument, to the desire to preserve the monument for its his-
Character and Its Origin, transl. Forster and Ghirardo, Oppositions 25 (Fall 1982):
torical significance to a given culture. This final stage in the 21-56, French translation: “Le Culte moderne des monuments”. Son essence et sa
evolution of the cult of monuments would cross national and genese (Paris: Seuil, 1984).
2
“The Modern Cult of Monuments: Its Character and Its Origin”, op. cit., 24.
social strata. Age, Riegl argues, is a ubiquitous phenomenon 3
Ibid, 1. Riegl probably drafted the first paragraph of the law defining the monu-
that knows no borders; its expression is accessible to all and ment.
4
Ibid, 21.
would overcome the nationalistic sentiments of his day. 5
Ibid, 21-23.
Riegl’s prediction that the cult of intentional monuments 6
Ibid, 21.
7
Ibid, 21.
as a trace of an archaic tradition would not survive a modern 8
Ibid, 24.
notion of history and was to be proved wrong. The World Wars 9
Ibid, 24-31. See also Françoise Choay, L’allegorie du patrimoine (Paris: Seuil,
1992) 128-131.
and totalitarian regimes of the 20th century led to the re-affir- 10
“The Modern Cult of Monuments: Its Character and Its Origin”, o cit., 24.
mation of the role and use of the intentional monument in the 11
Ibid, 21-31.
12
fabrication of national myths. Generally, Riegl’s historical This related foremost to architectural buildings but could also include the safety
measures taken in relation to other types monument i.e. the monuments should
determinism is of historical rather than analytical interest. not risk damaging an onlooker (falling stones etc.).
13
“The Modern Cult of Monuments,” however, does contain a “The Modern Cult of Monuments: Its Character and Its Origin”, o cit., 39-42.
14
Kurt W. Forster, “Monument/Memory and the Mortality of Architecture,”
valuable legacy. Riegl’s identification of the unintentional Oppositions 25 (1982): 10.
monument as a class remains a fruitful category for analytical 15
“The Modern Cult of Monuments: Its Character and Its Origin”, o cit., 24, 48.
16
Ibid, 42. For the reference to Siegfried Giedion see: Siegfried Giedion,
thinking; while his historical context prevented him from see- Mechanization Takes Command, a Contribution to Anonymous History. (Oxford:
ing the Euro-centric perspective of his historical schema, his Oxford University Press, 1948).
17
“The Modern Cult of Monuments: Its Character and Its Origin”, o cit., 43-44.
history of conservation clearly shows that the unintentional 18
For Riegl’s criticism of historicism see: Reynolds, Diana, Graham, “Alois Riegl and
monument was specific to Western culture. the Politics of Art History: Intellectual Traditions and Austrian Identity in Fin de
The internal contradictions that shift through “The Siecle Vienna,” PhD dissertation, University of California at San Diego: Ann Arbor
(UMI), 1997.
Modern Cult of Monuments” also reveal intriguing complexi- 19
“The Modern Cult of Monuments: Its Character and Its Origin”, o cit., 44.
ties that widen the notion of the monument. Throughout his
examination of the notion of the monument and its function in
the age of modernity, Riegl maintains that the monument’s pri-
79 80

También podría gustarte