Está en la página 1de 6

Equilibrium: History of the Concept

Till Duppe, Universit du Qubec Montral (UQAM), Montral, QC, Canada


2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

Abstract

Equilibrium analysis largely identies the scope of theory in todays economic research. This prominent place has several
historical origins. Before the notion was rst used, equilibrium arguments were already applied in early modern writings on
trade. Not before the late eighteenth century, the concept became part of the vocabulary of political economists. It was used as
an analogical and, moreover, normative concept referring to the natural order of the economy. At the end of the nineteenth
century, the concept gained analytical meaning, specically because of the difference between static and dynamic equilib-
rium. Between the 1940s and the 1960s, the concept grew into a metatheoretical notion as the corner stone of axiomatic
general equilibrium analysis, which in turn would become the bedrock of current mathematical modeling. Equally in game
theory, the concept is the main analytical tool, though not limited to competitive interactions in markets. It allows
formalizing institutional environments and strategic interaction on an individual and group level. In nearly all macroeco-
nomic modeling, general equilibrium theory continues to be the prevailing reference point.

Equilibrium analysis largely identies the scope of theory in seventeenth century. Since the form of argument is fairly
todays economic research. Since there are many economic simple, one could without doubt nd yet earlier uses. The
theories, the concept refers only vaguely to specic beliefs or discursive situation from which these arguments emerged was
ideas about economic reality. Instead, it provides cohesion to early modern writings on trade, mostly pamphlets written in
the economic way of modeling in the social sciences, and thus the context of the council of trade. Equilibrium arguments
corresponds with a style of reasoning typical for the discipline provided a rationale for xing quantitative measures such as
of economics (Hacking, 1992). price limits, tax levels, import quotas, etc. Previous arguments
The prominent place that the concept occupies in that used the Aristotelian and medieval concept of the just
economics today has several origins. Before the notion was rst price, lacked such a rationale. To give but one example:
used, equilibrium arguments were already applied in early William Petty, when speaking of the limit between a reason-
modern writings on trade. Not before the late eighteenth able rate of interest and illegitimate usury, argued that the
century, the concept became part of the vocabulary of political interest rate should be as high as the rent of land, for if not,
economists. It was used as an analogical and, moreover, nancial investment would soon outweigh agricultural
normative concept referring to the natural order of the production (Petty, 1899: 48). Similar arguments regarding
economy. At the end of the nineteenth century, the concept excess supply and demand can be found in the writings of
gained analytical meaning, specically because of the differ- Sir Dudley North or John Locke (Letwin, 1963: 198; Tieben,
ence between static and dynamic equilibrium. Between the 2012). Equilibrium arguments are a form of hypothetical
1940s and the 1960s, the concept grew into a metatheoretical reasoning that replaces normative arguments about economic
notion as the corner stone of axiomatic general equilibrium measures such as price ceilings or tax levels. They require
analysis, which in turn would become the bedrock of current a notion of interdependence of two or more economic vari-
mathematical modeling. Equally in game theory, the concept is ables, the change of one of which induces the change of the
the main analytical tool, though not limited to competitive other and vice versa. The causal mechanism of this endoge-
interactions in markets. It allows formalizing institutional nous change, however, must not be fully specied. Hence,
environments and strategic interaction on an individual and equilibrium arguments were present in economic writings
group level. In nearly all macroeconomic modeling, general before the concept was explicitly used in terms of a specic
equilibrium theory continues to be the prevailing reference ontology of the nature of economic order.
point despite its limited use for empirical analysis. Not all arguments involving interdependence, however, are
Since the concept functioned differently at each point of time, equilibrium arguments, as, for example, Francoise Quesnays
one better views its history as a sequence of transformations tableau conomique that traces the causal effects of growth in one
of different, not necessarily reducible scientic cultures in sector, agriculture, onto all others (Quesnay, 1766). Even
economics. The history of the concept is nevertheless signicant though equilibrium arguments do not require full causal
insofar as in current economic research as well as in economic explanations, they equally should be kept apart from identity
policy more recent and at the same time older meanings of the arguments that were also frequently used in seventeenth- and
concept are used interchangeably. eighteenth-century economic writings. The so-called Says law
might be the best-known example that states that (aggregate)
supply and demand cannot diverge because they are mutually
Early Forms of Equilibrium Arguments determined. Identities cannot be unequal and thus serve as
principles from which equilibrium arguments can be con-
Before the concept was used explicitly, equilibrium arguments structed. An example of a very inuential early equilibrium
can be traced back to early modern economic writings of the argument that shows the difference between identity,

912 International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition, Volume 7 http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.03081-6
Equilibrium: History of the Concept 913

equilibrium, and causality is Humes so-called price specie ow


The natural price . is, as it were, the central price, to which the prices
(1752: 82ff.). Hume argued that a trade surplus cannot be
of all commodities are continually gravitating. Different accidents
maintained in the long run, as mercantilist writers assumed, may sometimes keep them suspended a good deal above it, and
because the inow of gold would increase domestic prices that sometimes force them down even somewhat below it. But whatever
in turn leads to less export and more import until the balance may be the obstacles which hinder them from settling in this center
of payments is restored. The identity of price level and money of repose and continuance, they are constantly tending towards it.
Smith, 1961[1776]: 65
supply is assumed, the equilibrium argument is hypothetical,
and the actual causal mechanism of the economic agents who
respond to price differentials is unspecied. Gravitational forces of the market refer to the effects of
changes of demand (that is degrees of wants for conveniences
and of needs for necessities) given the limitations of produc-
Analogical Uses of the Concept of Equilibrium tion (that are determined by local natural resources, tech-
nology, capital maintenance, and labor costs). Such are the
In order to possess explanatory value, equilibrium arguments economic forces to be brought into balance by the price
must include an ontological dimension beyond hypothetical mechanism that imposes costs and benets on decisions of
reasoning: the nature of the causal mechanism that brings producers and consumers. Being in rivalry with one another,
about endogenous change must be specied. Classical political they react to price differentials.
economists established this explanatory value of the concept by Next to physical or celestial analogies, anatomic analogies
means of the analogy between economic and natural order. are also frequently used in economic writings of the eighteenth
Elements of the market economy, say, different parties of trade, century. After William Harveys discovery of blood circulation,
relate to one another like elements in other domains where the economic writers commonly described trade in anatomical
belief in an ordered system was already established. This terms. Money ows through the economy like blood through
analogical usage of the term was decisive for establishing the veins. Thomas Hobbes was one of the rst, John Pollexfen, Jacob
belief in an orderly sphere of the economy as an object of Vanderlint, Philip Cantillon, and others followed in calling the
systematic inquiry. public treasure the heart of the state and money its blood that
The very rst appearance of the concept in the history of makes its organs reach out to other states e.g., by paying armies
social thought is difcult to identify because the concept has (see Walter, 2011: 4047). This anatomical analogy held both
been already established in other than social writings where ways to the extent that the notion of the economy was habitually
it described mechanical movements, interstellar forces, used in medical treatises when one spoke of the economy of the
anatomic proportions, which often had, typical for eighteenth- body and its natural equilibrium. Diseases were dened in terms
century authors, also creationist connotations. The French of the divergence from this equilibrium, such that equilibrium
writer Pierre de Boisguilbert (16461714), to whom Spiegel took on older meanings of moderation and lack of excess.
assigns rst usage, used the term when comparing economic These analogical uses helped establishing the eld of
and divine order (Spiegel, 1991: 614). For him, equilibrium political economy as an inquiry into an orderly object of study.
refers to a state of opulence. He also used the analogy with It established the belief that certain systematic or persistent
mechanics according to the original Latin root of the word forces, regular in their operation, are at work in the economic
equal balance in order to explain the price mechanism: system, which is the most general feature of the concept of
equilibrium according to Milgate (2008). The analogy was put
forward against the belief that economic phenomena are
It is like a balance suspended in equilibrium because the weight is manifestations of the blind forces of power and thus are not
equal in each of the two scales. A hundred pounds of any material
whatever cannot receive an increase of even two pounds in one of the
intelligible or predictable in systematic terms. This contrast
two scales without destroying the equilibrium. This, then, is precisely with the concept of power will be present throughout further
what takes place with regard to the price of grain. An increase or transformations of the concept.
a diminution of twenty sacks at the market or staple house above or The analogical use also established the very prominent
below the ordinary supply of ve hundred sacks offered every week,
normative meaning of a state of harmony of interests in a free-
destroys the balance, and makes it fall immediately on one side.
Boisguilbert, 1966[1707]: 859 market society. Smiths natural price implied harmony between
the three classes of labor, capitalists, and landowners. His
analogy nourished the idea that once left alone, the economy
After such occasional uses in the early eighteenth century, spontaneously forms its inner order such that market inter-
the concept became part of the vocabulary of political econo- ventions seeking power over the economy disturb this natural
mists during the Scottish enlightenment of the late eighteenth order, and thus the harmony of interests. Free competition
century. While the concept was also used by James Steuart in allows the natural forces of the economy to bring about an
1769 (see Milgate, 2008), the locus classicus of the analogical orderly, harmonious, and thus desirable state of the economy.
concept of equilibrium is Adam Smith when speaking of the Even though Smith also propagated many government
gravitational force exerted by the natural price (Smith, 1961 responsibilities, he thought of free trade as the system of
[1776]: 60ff.). The natural price, according to Smith, reects natural liberty: complete resource mobility and free entry and
(long-run) production costs while the market price varies exit in all markets. His system of natural liberty referred to
according to short-term deviations of demand or supply. These institutions that induce rivalry between economic agents that
deviations are forced back to the natural price by means of are necessary for the gravitational forces of the market to be at
rivalry between either consumers or producers. work (Smith, 1961[1776]: 687).
914 Equilibrium: History of the Concept

Classical political economists hardly ever felt obliged to demand and supply in all goods and factor markets that each
spell out the analogy of the concept of equilibrium to such depend on the price of the good of this market and all other
extent that the nature of economic forces could be empirically goods and factor prices being either complements or substi-
tested or even analytically determined. In fact, if used solely in tutes. Equilibrium refers to a set of prices that solves all equa-
an analogical fashion without the hypothetical reasoning tions simultaneously.
referred to in the previous section, classical political economists Even if Walrass inspiration was a textbook by Louis Poinsot
added little to the normative arguments of natural law on the mechanical equilibrium of a solar system (Ingrao and
philosophers. In turn, the normative meaning of the concept of Israel, 1990: 88), and even if later in his life he defended his
equilibrium, until today, has never been fully argued for approach by an analogy between economic and mechanical
without analogical elements (see Dppe, 2011). concepts (scarcity and utility relate to one another like force
The fact that the equilibrium concept rather imported and energy, see Mirowski and Cook, 1990), Walras did not
familiarity into economic discourse than provided explana- believe that economic and natural phenomena are reducible to
tions of the market mechanism was still true when late- one another. He moved beyond analogical reasoning insofar he
nineteenth century neoclassical writers used the concept, such put emphasis on the common mathematical structure while
as William Stanley Jevons. His analogy was that of the equi- recognizing the ontological differences between these domains.
librium of prices and that of a pendulum: Accordingly, Walras distinguished, similar to Mill, between
pure, applied, and social economics, while only in the context
of pure economics, an equilibrium could be properly dened.
We can no more know nor measure gravity in its own nature than we
can measure a feeling; but, just as we measure gravity by its effects in Little ontological commitment was transmitted by Walrass
the motion of a pendulum, so we may estimate the equality or analytical concept of equilibrium. Instead, he opened the door
inequality of feelings by the decisions of the human mind. The will is to mathematical modeling, specically to linear algebra.
our pendulum, and its oscillations are minutely registered in the The aim of Walrass system was the representation of the
price lists of the markets.
Jevons, 1970[1871]: 11
interdependence of all markets. Agents all over the economy
that appear to be unrelated are connected by the price system.
Equilibrium thus contrasts to fragmentation of the economy, in
Already before Jevons, however, notably with John Stuart which case one could say very little about a market economy as
Mill, skepticism regarding the empirical merits of the analogy a whole. This interest in capturing interdependence is often
emerged. Mill emphasized that economic laws hold only under contrasted with Alfred Marshalls (1920[1890]) analysis of
very restrictive conditions that can, in contrast to natural laws, markets: the latter representing partial, the former general,
never be fully observed in reality (because of the absence of equilibrium theory. Marshall sought to understand the mech-
controlled experiments). Due to noneconomic interfering anism of single markets, ceteris paribus all effects on other
causes only tendencies toward states of equilibrium can be markets. What allowed Marshall to do so was a distinction
observed. The classical laws of the market are true only in the between causal factors being relevant for different periods of
abstract, that is, they are only true under certain suppositions, time (1890: Book V). He distinguished, rst, the market period
in which none but general causes causes common to the in which goods had been already produced, supply is thus
whole class of cases under consideration are taken into xed, such that prices depend solely on demand; second, the
account (Mill, 1844: 144145). In this fashion, Mill opened short-run period in which production can be expanded altering
the way to the analytical notion of the concept of equilibrium, some production factors, but not all due to prime costs; third,
specically by pointing to the signicant fact that initial in the long-run all production technologies can change, while
conditions of the equilibrium, in the concrete, may change on demand is stable. Consequently, as to whether or not one
the way, and that hence the static idea of a market equilibrium considers being in equilibrium depends on the period of time
must be supplemented with a theory of dynamic change (Mill, one considers. Such was Marshalls take on the problem of
1848: 421ff.). Thus, Mill introduced a distinction that was to dynamics the problem that the endogenous changes induced
remain present in all equilibrium analysis: the difference by a disequilibrium changes the initial conditions of equilib-
between static and dynamic equilibrium analysis. rium, such as income and technology.
Walrass instead, in his framework of general equilibrium
analysis, bypassed the problem of dynamic change by speaking
The Analytical Concept of Equilibrium of an auctioneer who identies the set of equilibrium prices
by crying out random prices before any transaction is taken
It was only in the last decades of the nineteenth century, (Jaffe, 1967). This comparison with the stock market was clearly
specically after the work of Lon Walras (18341910) that not an identication of the causes that bring prices into equi-
equilibrium became a theoretical concept that could be librium, as Marshall would have it, but the possibility of an
analyzed in its own terms without reference to other domains algorithm that describes the change of prices within his system
of research. Decisive was the idea of representing the economy of equations. The Walrasian auctioneer, as an analytical crea-
as a system of equations in Walrass Elements of Pure Economics tion, allowed for equilibrium theory to develop theoretical
(2003[1874]). Similar to nonconceptual uses of the word when problems of its own prior to its applications. When Walras
one speaks of a balance of payment to be in equilibrium, considered actual price changes, he drew back and referred once
equilibrium as the solution of a system of equations refers to again to a natural analogy, a lake agitated by the wind, saying
the state of market clearance where aggregate demand is equal that initial conditions are in continuous change due to the
to aggregate supply. Equations are separately dened for changes caused by a disequilibrium (Walras, 2003[1874]: 380).
Equilibrium: History of the Concept 915

Nature, no longer a source of the belief in an orderly domain, and uncertainty: the temporary equilibrium (Hicks, 1939).
changes faster than the market can adapt. Hicks specied the process by which an equilibrium comes
Next to the static and dynamic equilibrium, another about in sequential terms. He spoke of a market period called
analytical difference that became prominent from contrasting a week dened as the period in-between transactions that
Marshall and Walras was that of aggregation and disaggrega- allow for carrying out production plans. Equilibrium was thus
tion: Can the conditions of market equilibrium be traced down no longer dened in terms of long-run forces and short-run
to the individual level? Marshall assumed what is nowadays disturbances. Adaptations and decisions were sequentially
called a representative agent such that even the marginal utility separated. Insofar as at each transaction day a new equilibrium
of income was supposed to be the same across all income is achieved Hicks bypassed problems of the coordination of
levels. Walras equally started from aggregate market demand expectations. At each period of time there are different market
and supply functions, even if his set of equations could in clearing prices.
principle be spelled out in terms of disaggregated individual Also the normative dimension of the equilibrium concept
functions or so he and other neoclassical economists was heavily inuenced by these new problems of time, as is
assumed for a long time until the opposite was proven in the evident in Oskar Langes idea of market socialism (1938).
1970s, as we see below. Lange reinterpreted Walrass general equilibrium theory as an
In the hands of Walras, a signicant transformation of the economic theory of socialism with public ownership of
concept took place regarding its normative welfare dimension. production factors. The central planning bureau sets prices like
Perfect competition for Walras means that prices are indepen- a Walrasian auctioneer, observes excess demand and supply via
dent of demand and supply functions, i.e., they are given to inventory data, and reaches equilibrium by adapting factor
economic agents. Gone was the close link between rivalry and prices accordingly. Against this use of equilibrium analysis,
free-market institutions such that it was no longer obvious in Friedrich Hayek put forth a concept of competition that is
which institutional context equilibrium theory would apply. opposed to any notion of equilibrium: competitive institutions
This was indeed not the task of pure economics according to are preferable as they result in the most adaptive utilization of
Walras. As a result, the normative meaning of the concept of local knowledge. It is only in a continuously changing envi-
equilibrium was no longer the harmony of interests and the ronment, that is, in disequilibrium, that the price mechanism
natural system of liberty, but the absence of waste and the shows to be superior to a bureaucratic system (Hayek, 1945).
efcient use of resources as the formal implication of market
clearance. Neoclassical welfare economics is in fact less an
argument for specic economic institutions or policies, but the Axiomatic Equilibrium Analysis
development of criteria according to which various institutions
and policies, interventionist or not, could be evaluated. Between the 1940s and the 1960s the concept of equilibrium
became the central means by which mathematical modeling
was advanced, and conceptual and other literary economic
Equilibrium and Time theory were replaced. The concept of equilibrium became the
symbol of the culture of economics being different from other
The distinction between static and dynamic equilibrium social sciences (Dppe and Weintraub, 2014). The joint of this
remained the driving force of innovations involving the development was the application of the axiomatic approach in
concept of equilibrium in the rst half of the twentieth century. mathematics to general equilibrium theory. The early contri-
An important complication of the problem of dynamics was, butions to this development were mathematical existence
rather than income effects, the uncertainty of long-term proofs written by John von Neumann, John Nash, Kenneth
investment decisions that has short-term effects. An impor- Arrow, Grard Debreu, and Lionel McKenzie (using various
tant consequence of this uncertainty is that there is no reason to versions of Brouwers xed-point theorem, see Weintraub,
trust that prot rates are unique across all markets. And so the 1983; Debreu, 1987). This launched the period of several
concept of equilibrium was in the background of a range of decades of advancing mathematical tools in order to determine
institutional questions regarding monetary and business cycles axioms that are necessary to prove, next to existence, unique-
theories that were put forth by Austrian economists. Bhm- ness, stability, and the optimality of an equilibrium (Ingrao
Bawerk, for example, spoke of an intertemporal equilibrium and Israel, 1990). By the 1970s, denitions of equilibrium
considering both long-term and short-term plans simulta- conditions (the axioms) became a necessary requirement for all
neously in a trade off between current and future consumption economic theory.
(Bhm-Bawerk, 1959[1899]). In further course, including The axiomatization of equilibrium theory was, similar to
uncertainty in equilibrium analysis, most notably after John mathematics at the same time, coined by an image conict
Maynard Keynes, generated a whole bunch of new analytical (Dalmedico, 2001). In the spirit of John von Neumann, several
problems that were largely unknown to political economists, mathematical economists understood the axiomatic approach
and, in further course, only vaguely linked with traditional as a clarication of the behavioral and institutional elements of
price theory. What came to be labeled as macroeconomics equilibrium theory: producers and technologies, consumers
gained shape in a certain distance to equilibrium analysis. and commodities. Axioms are seen as basic ontological prop-
It was not before John Hicks (190489), in response to the erties that must be true for an equilibrium in a competitive
work of Lindahl and Hayek, and in trying to reconcile economy to possibly exist, to be empirically determined
Keynesian and Walrasian theories, that a different interpreta- (uniqueness), to be stable, and to have desirable welfare
tion of equilibrium was introduced to solve problems of time properties (optimality). The early existence proofs were
916 Equilibrium: History of the Concept

considered a preliminary exercise that would generate new disappointed. Mathematical economists such as Frank Hahn,
solutions to traditional questions (Arrow, 1968). The success of however, considered these negative results most valuable
the axiomatic method would depend heavily on the plausi- insofar as they allow for a falsication of the beliefs that were
bility of its axioms as being descriptive of economic reality. traditionally linked with the notion of equilibrium, above all
Specically the rationality of optimizing agents emerged as the its normative aspects (Hahn, 1973). In terms of the present
pivotal condition of equilibrium. article, axiomatic analysis of equilibrium theory helped cor-
According to another image of the axiomatization of equi- recting the beliefs that the analogical concept of equilibrium
librium theory, however, the mathematical structure of the has established.
theory is only loosely related to its possible interpretations.
Innovations of new mathematical tools can then enlarge, limit,
or create new forms of explanations on the level of economic Game Theoretical Concepts of Equilibrium
theory. Several mathematical economists, many of which were
associated with Grard Debreu, focused on the development of After John von Neumanns and Oskar Morgensterns seminal
new mathematical tools such as measure theory and nonstan- book, The Theory of Games and Economic Behavior (1944), also
dard analysis, among others. The guiding epistemic virtue was game theory, with a certain delay, transformed the concept of
mathematical generality (which does not necessarily correlate equilibrium. One research question that has been pursuit
with greater economic applicability): topology being more during the 1960s was specically formative, that of core
general than, for example, differential equations. As questions convergence. The core is an equilibrium concept going back to
of stability, among others, required tools that are lower in this Edgeworths theory of exchange: it includes all allocations, for
hierarchy than those necessary for existence proofs, the latter which no subset of individuals would be better off, if they
played a greater role than the former. The pivotal axioms that separated from the other individuals (in the case of two indi-
emerged from this axiomatic approach were properties such as viduals, the core excludes those allocations, which leaves
convexity, monotonicity, differentiability, continuity rather individuals worse than alone). The question of core conver-
than the behavioral notion of rationality. Moreover, equilib- gence was whether or not, once the amount of individuals
rium analysis was not related to competitive institutions, increase, the set of core allocations shrinks toward the
a concept that does, for example, not appear in Debreus Theory competitive price solution. Core convergence thus opened
of Value (1959). The axiomatic method results in the separation a path to integrate game theory in the tradition of economic
of mathematical and economic reasoning that has indenite theory enlarging the scope of equilibrium theory from
and uncontrolled effects on the latter. competition to strategic behavior. In fact, competitive behavior
This image conict was hardly ever confronted such that appeared to be a special case of noncooperative games
there was never a consensus among practitioners in economic oceanic games, as Milnor and Shapley called them (1961).
theory what the exact status of axioms is: hypothesis, basic Core convergence helped in rescuing the standards of
ontological property, or auxiliary construct for creating mathematical modeling that were established in general equi-
a plurality of contextual theories (Dppe, 2012). Accordingly, librium theory where they led into the rather negative results
the concept of equilibrium, until today, plays a double role in mentioned above (Rizvi, 1994).
economic theory: it refers to the analytical solvability of Historically speaking, this revival of game theory in the
a model, and at the same time to the solution concept of actual 1960s bore aspects of irony. The core referred back to another,
economic problems by modeling the consequences for an slightly more general concept in cooperative game theory, the
entire system. After the diffusion of general equilibrium models stable set. Cooperative game theory allows for some coalitions
in the entire discipline during the 1970s, the concept drove to be binding even if some individuals would be better off
a wedge between the analysis of theoretical structures and the without partaking in this coalition. This was the central equi-
elaboration of economic interpretations. librium concept in von Neumanns and Morgensterns book
Within the inner circles of mathematical economists, (1944). Mostly because of the interpretations of the Austrian
however, the research program of axiomatic general equilib- trained economist Morgenstern, game theory was initially
rium theory showed rather negative results: stability could not presented in contrast to competitive equilibrium as the latter
be specied, uniqueness of an equilibrium required ad-hoc excluded the exertion of strategy and power. This opposition
assumptions that were considered rather strong, and at the was forgotten once competition was considered to be analyti-
top of it, in 1974, Hugo Sonnenschein, Rolf Mantel, and cally reducible to game theory.
Debreu showed that excess demand functions lack structure The most dominant equilibrium concept in game theory,
even if one assumes well-behaved, i.e., rational individual however, is the noncooperative solution concept named after
preferences. The theory imposes little structure on empirical John Nash: no player can gain by changing behavior unilaterally
data. Even simple questions of comparative statics (such as the taking into account the behavior of other players. The existence
effects of tax cut on demand and supply) that were already by proof of such equilibrium was an inspiration also for Arrow and
the 1960s and still are standard in economic education could Debreu to proof existence in general equilibrium theory (Dppe,
no longer be considered rigorous. One has to impose addi- 2012). Further renements of the Nash equilibrium became
tional structure in order to generate empirically denite results central to all game theory, causing an entire industry of research
(such as constant elasticity of utility functions, a specic elaborating information constraints imposed on all or a subset of
income distribution, and the like). players: different kind of games (asymmetric games, sequential
By the mid-1970s, the hopes of early post-World War II games, mixed strategies, evolutionary games where players act
years for the future of general equilibrium theory were largely according to (genetic) traits), different market forms (for
Equilibrium: History of the Concept 917

example, Cournot equilibrium in a duopolistic market, or Lin- Colander, David, 2010. The economics profession, the nancial crisis, and method.
dahl equilibrium as a solution to public good problems), but also Journal of Economic Methodology 17 (4), 419427.
Dalmedico, Amy D., 2001. An image conict in mathematics after 1945. In:
different types of auctions. Game theory, much in contrast to
Bottazzini, U., Dalmedico, A.D. (Eds.), Changing Images in Mathematics: From the
general equilibrium theory, is thus considered descriptive of French Revolution to the New Millenium. Routledge, London and New York,
behavioral content and institutional contexts. None of its insti- pp. 223253.
tutional applications, however, replace the concept of Nash Debreu, Grard, 1986. Theoretic models: mathematical form and economic content.
equilibrium. Econometrica 54 (6), 12591270.
Debreu, Grard, 1987. Existence of general equilibrium. In: Durlauf, Steven N.,
Game theory also proved to be crucial for the import of new Blume, Lawrence E. (Eds.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics.
empirical methods into economics, such as cognitive theories and Debreu, Gerard, 1959. Theory of Value: An Axiomatic Analysis of Economic Equilib-
experimental methods. The results, however, concern the rium. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT.
behavioral assumptions, but not the concept of equilibrium itself. Dppe, Till, 2011. How economic methodology became a separate science. Journal of
Economic Methodology 18 (2), 163176.
It is still difcult to imagine a theory identiable as economic
Dppe, Till, 2012. Arrow and Debreu de-homogenized. Journal of the History of
theory without reference to the concept of equilibrium. Economic Thought 34 (4), 491514.
Dppe, Till, Weintraub, E. Roy, 2014. Finding Equilibrium: Arrow, Debreu, McKenzie
and the Problem of Scientic Credit. Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Equilibrium Analysis in Todays Macroeconomics Hacking, Ian, 1992. Style for historians and philosophers. Studies in History and
Philosophy of Science Part A 23 (1), 120.
Hahn, Frank, 1973. On the Notion of Equilibrium in Economics. Cambridge University
Despite the fact that competitive general equilibrium analysis, Press, Cambridge.
as shown above, has turned out to imply little for empirical Hayek, Friedrich A., 1945. The use of knowledge in society. American Economic
research, it continues to be the sheer exclusive reference point, Review 35 (4), 519530.
Hicks, John R., 1939. Value and Capital. Clarendon Press, Oxford.
in combination with econometric methods, for all macroeco-
Hume, David, 1752. Political Discourses. Oxford University.
nomics theories. General equilibrium theory has been omni- Ingrao, Bruna, Israel, Georgio, 1990. The Invisible Hand: Economic Equilibrium in the
present ever since the work of Robert Lucas, Thomas J. Sargent, History of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Edward C. Prescott, and among others (Snowdon and Vane, Jaffe, William, 1967. Walras theory of tatonnement: a critique of recent interpretations.
2005). It is used as the analytical solution to so-called Journal of Political Economy 75 (1), 119.
Jevons, William S., 1970[1871]. Theory of Political Economy. Edited from the second
dynamic stochastic general equilibrium models. These ed. (1879) by R.D.C. Black. Penguin, Harmondsworth.
models use the general equilibrium framework subject to Lange, Oskar, Taylor, Fred, 1964[1938]. On the Economic Theory of Socialism.
stochastic shocks in order to explain historical time series data McGraw Hill, New York.
given calibrated exogenous variables. The analytical problems Letwin, William, 1963. The Origins of Scientic Economics: English Economic Thought
16601776. Methuen, London.
stated in axiomatic equilibrium analysis are bypassed by
Marshall, Alfred, 1920[1890]. Principles of Economics, eighth ed. Macmillan, London.
imposing structure on economic agents (usually CobbDoug- Milgate, Murray, 2008. The development of the concept of equilibrium. In:
las functions, which brings back the representative agent of Durlauf, Steven N., Blume, Lawrence E. (Eds.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of
Marshalls partial equilibrium analysis). Economics, second ed. Palgrave Macmillan.
After the 2008 nancial crisis, dynamic stochastic general Mill, John Stuart, 1844. Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy,
1874, reprinted, second ed. Augustus M. Kelley, New York.
equilibrium (DSGE) models and with it the imperative of Mill, John Stuart, 1848. Principles of Political Economy, 1871 (reprinted 1909), sixth
equilibrium analysis was put under heavy attack (Colander, ed. Longmans, Green & Company, London.
2010). Even though in newly emerging elds such as in econ- Milnor, John W., Shapley, Lloyd S., 1961. Value of Large Games, II: Oceanic Games.
ophysics the concept of equilibrium appears to be expendable, RAND Memorandum.
Mirowski, Philip, Cook, Pamela, 1990. Walrass economics and mechanics: trans-
since agent-based simulation techniques bypass analytical
lation, commentary, context. In: Samuels, Warren (Ed.), Economics as Discourse.
solvability of mathematical modeling, the great mass of Kluwer, pp. 189215.
macroeconomic theory is far from incorporating these tools Neumann, John von, Morgenstern, Oskar, 1944. Theory of Games and Economic
and moving away from equilibrium analysis. Behavior. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
Petty, William, 1899. In: Hull, Charles H. (Ed.), The Economic Writings of Sir William
Petty: Together with the Observations upon the Bills of Mortality (More Probably by
See also: Axiomatic Theories; Cooperative Game Theory; Captain John Graunt). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Discipline Formation in the Social Sciences; Economics, Quesnay, Franois, 1766. Analyse de la formule arithmtique du Tableau conomique
History of; Game Theory: Noncooperative Games; Game de la distribution annuelle dune nation agricole. Journal de lAgriculture, du
Theory; Liberalism: Political Doctrine and Impact on Social Commerce et des Finances 5 (3), 1141.
Rizvi, Abu Turab S., 1994. Game theory to the Rescue? Contributions to Political
Science; Political Economy, History of; Social Mechanism; Economy 13, 128.
Welfare Economics. Smith, Adam, 1961[1776]. In: Cannan, E. (Ed.), An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes
of the Wealth of Nations. Methuen, London.
Snowdon, Brian, Vane, Howard R., 2005. Modern Macroeconomics: Its Origins,
Development and Current State. Edward Elgar.
Bibliography Spiegel, Henry W., 1991. The Growth of Economic Thought, third ed. Duke University
Press, Durham.
Arrow, Kenneth J., 1968. Economic equilibrium. In: International Encyclopedia of the Tieben, Bert, 2012. The Concept of Equilibrium in Different Economic Traditions: An
Social Sciences, vol. 2. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Reprinted in The Historical Investigation. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, UK.
Collected Papers of Kenneth J. Arrow. Walras, Lon, 2003[1874]. Elements of Pure Economics: Or the Theory of Social
Bhm-Bawerk, Eugen, 1959[1899]. Capital and Interest. Reprinted. Libertarian Press, Wealth. Routledge, London.
South Holland, IL. Walter, Ryan, 2011. A Critical History of the Economy: On the Birth of the National and
Boisguilbert, Pierre de, 1966[1707]. Trait de la nature, culture, commerce et intrt International Economies. Abingdon, Routledge, Oxon.
des grains. In: Pierre de Boisguilbert ou la Naissance de lconomie Politique, 2 Weintraub, E. Roy, 1983. The existence of a competitive equilibrium: 19301954.
vols. Institut National Dtudes Dmographiques, Paris, pp. 827878. Journal of Economic Literature 21 (1), 139.

También podría gustarte