Está en la página 1de 9

Opinion

Interoceptive inference, emotion, and


the embodied self
Anil K. Seth
Sackler Centre for Consciousness Science and School of Engineering and Informatics, University of Sussex, Brighton, BN1 9QJ, UK

The concept of the brain as a prediction machine has Representations of physiological conditions have fre-
enjoyed a resurgence in the context of the Bayesian brain quently been associated with basic pre-reflective forms
and predictive coding approaches within cognitive sci- of selfhood [11], with the AIC occupying a central role on
ence. To date, this perspective has been applied primari- some views [13]. Selfhood is a constellation concept that
ly to exteroceptive perception (e.g., vision, audition), and involves not only representation and control of physiologi-
action. Here, I describe a predictive, inferential perspec- cal homeostasis, but also the experience of owning and
tive on interoception: interoceptive inference conceives identifying with a particular body, the emergence of a first-
of subjective feeling states (emotions) as arising from person perspective, intention and agency, and metacogni-
actively-inferred generative (predictive) models of the tive aspects that relate to the subjective I and the narra-
causes of interoceptive afferents. The model generalizes tive linking of episodic memories over time [17,18]. Here, I
appraisal theories that view emotions as emerging apply the framework of interoceptive inference to the
from cognitive evaluations of physiological changes, experience of body ownership (EBO) as a central aspect
and it sheds new light on the neurocognitive mecha- of selfhood, proposing on the basis of recent data [19,20]
nisms that underlie the experience of body ownership that EBO is shaped by predictive multisensory integration
and conscious selfhood in health and in neuropsychiatric
illness. Glossary
The predictive brain, body, and self Active inference: an extension of PC (and part of the free energy principle),
The view that prediction and error correction provide which says that agents can suppress prediction errors by performing actions to
bring about sensory states in line with predictions.
fundamental principles for understanding brain operation Augmented reality: a technique in which virtual images can be combined with
is gaining increasing traction within the cognitive and real-world real-time visual input to create hybrid perceptual scenes that are
brain sciences. In the renascent guise of predictive coding usually presented to a subject via a head-mounted display.
Appraisal theories of emotion: a long-standing tradition, dating back to James
(PC see Glossary) or predictive processing, perceptual (but not Lange), according to which emotions depend on cognitive interpreta-
content is seen as resulting from probabilistic, knowledge- tions of physiological changes.
Emotion: an affective state with psychological, experiential, behavioral, and
driven inference on the external causes of sensory signals
visceral components. Emotional awareness refers to conscious awareness of an
[14]. Here, this framework is applied to interoception, the emotional state.
sense of the internal physiological condition of the body [5], Experience of body ownership (EBO): the experience of certain parts of the
world as belonging to ones body. EBO can be distinguished into that related to
in order to elaborate a model of emotion as interoceptive body parts (e.g., a hand) and a global sense of identification with a whole body.
inference [69]. Interoceptive predictive coding equiva- Free energy principle: a generalization of PC according to which organisms
lently here, interoceptive inference is hypothesised to minimize an upper bound on the entropy of sensory signals (the free energy).
Under specific assumptions, free energy translates to prediction error.
engage an extended autonomic neural substrate with em- Generative model: a probabilistic model that links (hidden) causes and data,
phasis on the anterior insular cortex (AIC) as a compara- usually specified in terms of likelihoods (of observing some data given their
tor. This view extends alternative frameworks for causes) and priors (on these causes). Generative models can be used to
generate inputs in the absence of external stimulation.
understanding emotion [1014] by proposing that emotion- Interoception: the sense of the internal physiological condition of the body.
al content is generated by active top-down inference of the Interoceptive sensitivity: a characterological trait that reflects individual sensi-
causes of interoceptive signals in a predictive coding con- tivity to interoceptive signals, usually operationalized via heartbeat detection
tasks.
text. It also extends previous models of insular cortex as Predictive coding (PC): a data processing strategy whereby signals are repre-
supporting error-based learning of feeling states and un- sented by generative models. PC is typically implemented by functional archi-
certainty [15] and as responding to interoceptive mis- tectures in which top-down signals convey predictions and bottom-up signals
convey prediction errors.
matches that underlie anxiety [16]. Rubber hand illusion (RHI): a classic experiment in which the experience of
body ownership is manipulated via perceptual correlations such that a fake
(i.e., rubber) hand is experienced as part of a subjects body.
Corresponding author: Seth, A.K. (a.k.seth@sussex.ac.uk).
Selfhood: the experience of being a distinct, holistic entity, capable of global
Keywords: interoception; predictive coding; emotion; experience of body ownership;
self-control and attention, possessing a body and a location in space and time
rubber hand illusion; active inference.
[64]. Selfhood operates on multiple levels from basic physiological represen-
1364-6613/$ see front matter tations to metacognitive and narrative aspects.
2013 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2013.09.007 Subjective feeling states: consciously experienced emotional states that under-
lie emotional awareness.
Von Economo neurons (VENs): long-range projection neurons found selectively
in hominid primates and certain other species. VENs are found preferentially in
the AIC and ACC.

Trends in Cognitive Sciences, November 2013, Vol. 17, No. 11 565


Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences November 2013, Vol. 17, No. 11

(A) Predicon error

R1 R2 R3
Precision weighng
g
(B) Predicon

TRENDS in Cognitive Sciences

Figure 1. Functional architecture of predictive coding. (A) A schematic of hierarchical predictive coding across three cortical regions; the lowest on the left (R1) and the
highest on the right (R3). Bottom-up projections (red) originate from error units (light orange) in superficial cortical layers and terminate on state units (light blue) in the
deep (infragranular) layers of their targets, whereas top-down projections (dark blue) that convey predictions originate in deep layers and project to superficial layers of
their targets. Prediction errors are associated with precisions (inverse variances), which determine the relative influence of bottom-up and top-down signal flow. Top-down
precision weighting (dashed lines) regulates the post-synaptic gain of prediction-error projection neurons possibly by neuromodulation. Triangles represent pyramidal
(projection) neurons; circles represent inhibitory interneurons. Solid black lines depict local circuit interactions wherein descending predictions are resolved with ascending
prediction errors. (B) The influence of precisions on Bayesian inference and predictive coding. The curves represent probability distributions over the value of a sensory
signal (x-axis). On the left, high precision-weighting of sensory signals (red) enhances their influence on the posterior (green) and expectation (dotted line) as compared to
the prior (blue). On the right, low precision-weighting of sensory signals has the opposite effect on posteriors and expectations. Adapted from [6].

of self-related signals across interoceptive and exterocep- the causes of sensory signals. According to PC, the brain is
tive domains. continuously attempting to minimize the discrepancy or
Overall, the model described here provides a unified prediction error between its inputs and its emerging
view of self-related processing relevant to emotional models of the causes of these inputs via neural computa-
awareness and EBO, and carries implications for under- tions approximating Bayesian inference (Figure 1 and
standing specific neuropsychiatric disorders. Box 1). Importantly, prediction errors can be minimized
either by updating generative models (perceptual infer-
Predictive inference and perception ence and learning; changing the model to fit the world) or
The concept of PC overturns classical notions of perception by performing actions to bring about sensory states in line
as a largely bottom-up process of evidence accumulation with predictions (active inference; changing the world to
or feature detection, proposing instead that perceptual fit the model). In most incarnations these processes are
content is specified by top-down predictive signals that assumed to unfold continuously and simultaneously,
emerge from hierarchically organized generative models of underlining a deep continuity between perception and

Box 1. PC, free energy, and active inference


PC has a long history, originating with the insights of von Helmholtz posteriors at one level form the priors at one level lower, thus
and reaching recent prominence in the Bayesian brain hypothesis enabling priors to be induced from the data stream itself (empirical
[1,4]. The idea is that, in order to support adaptive responses, the Bayes). Applied to cortical networks, PC interprets bottom-up signals
brain must discover information about the likely causes of sensory as conveying prediction errors and top-down signals as conveying
signals (i.e., perception) without direct access to these causes, using predictions (Figure 1). Although unequivocal neural evidence for PC is
only information in the flux of sensory signals themselves [2]. still lacking, a growing body of supportive data details how perceptual
According to PC, this is accomplished via probabilistic inference on content and underlying neural responses can be shaped by pre-
the causes of sensory signals, computed according to Bayesian stimulus expectations [1,4,42].
principles. This means estimating the probable causes of data (the Key to PC is the minimization of prediction error across hierarchical
posterior) given observed conditional probabilities (likelihoods) levels. This can be accomplished either by updating generative
and prior beliefs about probable causes. This, in turn, means models to accommodate unexpected sensory signals or by perform-
inducing a predictive or generative model of the sensory data. ing actions to confirm sensory predictions (active inference, [21]). This
Although exact Bayesian inference is computationally challenging duality underlines a strong continuity between perception, action,
and often intractable, a variety of approximate methods exist. Within and imagination [68]. Also important is that prediction errors are
neuroscience, these approximations have been elaborated in Fris- associated with precisions (Figure 1), so that dynamic precision-
tons free energy principle [2,65], which, following seminal work by weighting (for example by attention) can modulate the balance
Hinton and colleagues [66,67], shows how generative models can be between top-down and bottom-up signal flow (e.g., low precision on
induced from data by assuming that the brain minimizes a bound on error signals corresponds to high confidence in top-down prior
the evidence for this data (the free energy, which under simplifying beliefs). The present framework generalizes PC to interoception,
(Gaussian) assumptions is equivalent to prediction error). The proposing that affective states depend on active inference of
generalization of Bayes theorem to a hierarchical context implies that interoceptive responses.

566
Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences November 2013, Vol. 17, No. 11

action. Prediction errors are associated with precisions, can be productively understood through the lens of PC. In
which determine their influence on subsequent hierarchi- this view, interoceptive inference involves hierarchically
cal processing. For example, precision weighting cascading top-down interoceptive predictions that counter-
(possibly implemented by post-synaptic gain modulation flow with bottom-up interoceptive prediction errors. Sub-
of prediction error units) can modulate the extent to jective feeling states experienced emotions are
which prediction errors are resolved by updating genera- hypothesized to depend on the integrated content of these
tive models or by performing actions [21]. This leads to an predictive representations across multiple levels [6].
interpretation of attention as the optimization of precision Following PC principles, interoceptive prediction errors
weighting, balancing the relative influence of prediction can be suppressed both by modifying predictions and by
errors and prior expectations on perceptual inference [2]. transcribing these predictions into reference points for
PC has been elaborated principally in the context of autonomic reflexes that regulate physiological homeosta-
exteroception; that is, to predictive modelling of external sis, as recently suggested by Gu and colleagues [9]. This
states of the world. However, one of the most relevant role for active inference, which extends previous presenta-
features of the world for a particular organism is the tions of this model [68], directly parallels PC formulations
organism itself [11,22]. This reflects a long-standing notion for motor control (e.g. [29]) which highlight descending
that mental representations of selfhood are ultimately corticospinal signals as instantiating proprioceptive pre-
grounded in representations of the body, with the internal dictions that engage classical motor reflexes. Precisions
physiological milieu providing a primary reference a play a key role here: descending predictions can engage
material me [13] that supports adaptive interaction motor or autonomic reflexes only if the corresponding error
with the environment. From a PC perspective, this implies signals have diminished impact on hierarchical processing
that an organism should maintain well-adapted predictive via transiently low precision weighting, which corresponds
models of its own physical body (its position, morphology, to decreased attention to these error signals. Without this
etc.) and of its internal physiological condition. This entails transient modulation, precise prediction errors would lead
inducing generative models of the causes of those signals to revision of predictions rather than to action [29]. This
most likely to be me [22] across interoceptive and extero- implies that active interoceptive inference depends on the
ceptive domains, a framework that views emotion as selective attenuation of attention to interoceptive predic-
interoceptive inference and provides a unifying mecha- tion errors.
nism for self-representation at multiple levels, including Interoceptive predictions arise from multiple hierarchi-
perhaps especially those related to EBO. cal levels, with higher levels integrating interoceptive,
proprioceptive and exteroceptive cues in formulating des-
Interoceptive inference and emotion cending predictions. These multimodal predictions under-
Interoceptive concepts of emotion were crystallized by write emotional responses to exteroceptive cues (which
James and Lange [10], who argued that emotions arise may include socially salient signals, see later). In short,
from perceptions of changes in the body. This approach interoceptive predictive coding (inference) proposes that
evolved into appraisal theories, which recognise that emotional content is determined by active inference on the
explicit cognitions and beliefs about the causes of physio- likely internal and external causes of changes in the phys-
logical changes influence subjective feeling states and iological condition of the body (Figure 2).
emotional behaviour [23]. Schachter and Singer [24] fa-
mously demonstrated that injections of adrenaline, proxi- Evidence for interoceptive inference
mally causing a state of physiological arousal, would give Although there is not yet any direct confirmatory evidence
rise to either anger or elation depending on the context for interoceptive inference (as for PC generally, see [1]),
(an irritated or elated confederate). This observation was supportive data are steadily accumulating. Much of these
formalized in their two factor theory, in which emotional data rest on assuming a central role for the anterior insular
experience is determined by the combination of physiologi- cortex (AIC), operating within a rich functional network
cal change and cognitive appraisal, that is, emotion as [30], both as a comparator that registers top-down predic-
interpreted bodily arousal (see [25] for a precursor). More tions against bottom-up prediction errors and as a source of
than a century after James and Lange, there is now a anticipatory visceromotor control [69,15,16]. Structural-
consensus that emotions are psychological states that ly, the AIC is ideally placed both to detect and to cause
encompass behavioural, experiential, and visceral changes changes in physiological condition, and to integrate inter-
[23,2628]. This attitude underpins several contemporary oceptive and exteroceptive signals; functionally, it
frameworks for understanding emotion and its relation to instantiates interoceptive representations accessible to
cognition and self [1113], discussed further below. conscious awareness and is associated with processes that
Despite the above insights, interoception has remained involve visceral representation, interoception, and emo-
generally understood along feed-forward lines, similar to tional awareness relevant to selfhood (Box 2).
classical evidence accumulation theories of exteroception Several functional MRI (fMRI) studies have shown
[23,28]. This assumption is however challenged by evi- anticipatory and prediction error responses within the
dence of substantial cross-talk between levels of viscero- AIC. For example, the AIC is activated by anticipation
sensory representation, including top-down cortical and of painful [31] and affect-laden touch [32], and AIC
behavioural influences to brainstem and spinal centres responses encode both predicted pain and pain prediction
[26]. Informed by this emerging picture, I suggest that error within a single task [33]. Similarly, in a gambling
the role of interoception in shaping emotion and selfhood task, the AIC has been shown to encode both predicted risk
567
Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences November 2013, Vol. 17, No. 11

World

Generave Motor
Extero PE
model control
Desired /
inferred state
Generave Autonomic
Intero PE
Salience model control
network

Body
Corollary discharge
TRENDS in Cognitive Sciences

Figure 2. A model of interoceptive inference. In the model, emotional responses depend on continually-updated predictions of the causes of interoceptive input. Starting
with a desired or inferred physiological state (which is itself subject to update based on higher-level motivational and goal-directed factors), generative models are engaged
which predict interoceptive (and exteroceptive) signals via corollary discharge. Applying active inference, prediction errors (PEs) are transcribed into actions via
engagement of classical reflex arcs (motor control) and autonomic reflexes (autonomic control). The resulting prediction error signals are used to update the (functionally
coupled) generative models and the inferred/desired state of the organism. (At high hierarchical levels these generative models merge into a single multimodal model.)
Interoceptive predictions are proposed to be generated, compared, and updated within a salience network (orange shading) anchored on the anterior insular and anterior
cingulate cortices (AIC, ACC) that engage brainstem regions as targets for visceromotor control and relays of afferent interoceptive signals. Sympathetic and
parasympathetic outflow from the AIC and ACC are in the form of interoceptive predictions that enslave autonomic reflexes (e.g., heart/respiratory rate, smooth muscle
behaviour), just as proprioceptive predictions enslave classical motor reflexes in PC formulations of motor control [9]. This process depends on the transient attenuation of
the precision of interoceptive (and proprioceptive) PE signals. Blue (red) arrows signify top-down (bottom-up) connections respectively.

and risk prediction error [34]. Holle et al. found AIC (e.g., anger) elicits behavioural responses from others, the
activation on viewing movies of people scratching, with detection of which could serve to confirm predictions of
the degree of activation correlating with the subjective interoceptive condition. This provides a nice link to predic-
level of reported itchiness [35]. Here, AIC responses plau- tive models of social interaction [38,39].
sibly reflect a conflict between predicted and actual inter- Supportive evidence is also provided by studies that
oceptive responses given anticipated itch, which suggests manipulate interoceptive feedback. Early evidence showed
an engagement of AIC in predictive inference related to that false cardiac feedback enhanced subjective ratings of
mirror-system activity and empathy [36]. Using the neu- emotive stimuli [40]. This was later confirmed by Gray and
roeconomic ultimatum game, Xiang and colleagues colleagues, who found that false cardiac feedback led to
showed that subjects used Bayesian rules to update increased fMRI responses in the right AIC and that en-
expected feelings given economic outcomes, and that feel- hanced AIC activity during false feedback correlated with
ing prediction errors (when measured using variance) increased emotional salience attributed to previously un-
scaled parametrically with AIC activation [37]. These threatening stimuli [41]. Further evidence showing the
studies support the idea that interoceptive inference influence of false interoceptive feedback on the experience
extends into social contexts to explain emotional behav- of body ownership is described below. Taken together with
iour. For example, the expression of an emotional state the structural and functional attributes of the AIC (Box 2),

Box 2. The anterior insula cortex and interoception


The human insular cortex is found bilaterally beneath the temporal information integration and so may underlie the efficient registration
and frontal lobes, enjoying widespread bidirectional connectivity to of interoceptive prediction and prediction error signals. In PC, top-
parietal, frontal, and limbic regions [30]. Interoceptive pathways down predictions are suggested to originate in infragranular
have their primary cortical representation within the insula, which pyramidal cells (Figure 1), consistent with the layer V predominance
contains a viscerotopic map [69]. A posterior-to-anterior gradient of VENs in the AIC [8,9,73].
has been proposed, whereby posterior regions support primary The AIC is engaged in a wide range of processes that share as
(objective) mappings of interoceptive signals, whereas the anterior common factors visceral representation, interoception, and emotional
insula (AIC) supports secondary re-representations that underlie awareness [6,9,13,26]. Importantly, the AIC (particularly on the right)
subjective access [9,12,13] and integration of interoceptive, motiva- appears to support conscious access to both interoceptive informa-
tional, and exteroceptive signals [6,70]. The AIC is closely connected tion as reflected in subjective emotional states (though see [43,74])
structurally and functionally with the anterior cingulate cortex (ACC) and to associated representations of how encoded objects and
as part of a cortical salience network [71], though they can be contexts relate to the biological self [15,75]. Distinct axes of
functionally differentiated [70], so that the AIC can be considered a interoceptive information map onto specific insula sub-regions giving
limbic sensory area and the ACC a limbic motor area [13,70]. These rise to dissociable emotional feeling states [76]. Also, individual
areas together engage subcortical regions, such as the periaque- differences in interoceptive sensitivity (IS), as measured by heartbeat
ductal gray matter and parabrachial nucleus, as targets for viscer- detection, are predicted by AIC activation and morphometry, and are
omotor control and relays for viscerosensory afferents, as well as also associated with reported emotional symptoms [12] and suscept-
many other areas related to self and emotion, including the ibility to illusions of selfhood (see main text).
amygdala, nucleus accumbens, and orbitofrontal cortex. Interest- These structural and functional attributes, when considered
ingly, the AIC contains a high density of von Economo neurons together with evidence for prediction error processing, strongly
(VENs) [72], which have been associated frequently though circum- suggest the AIC as a locus for comparator mechanisms that underlie
stantially with conscious awareness and selfhood [8,13,73]. VENs interoceptive inference, in turn supporting emotional awareness and
are large projection neurons well suited for rapid long-range consciously accessible integrated self-representations.

568
Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences November 2013, Vol. 17, No. 11

these data provide indirect support for interoceptive infer- body-ownership, are likely to operate at relatively
ence and the central involvement of the AIC in prediction abstract multisensory or amodal levels. Thus,
error registration underlying subjective feeling states. Ad- statistical correlations among highly precision-weighted
ditional experiments, perhaps based on designs utilized in sensory signals (vision, touch) could overcome prediction
exteroceptive contexts (e.g., [42]), are needed to test more errors in a different modality (proprioception), leading to a
directly interoceptive inference and the proposed role of revised multisensory predictive model that minimizes the
the AIC. overall level of self-related precision-weighted prediction
error by incorporating the fake hand as part of the self-
Relation to other models of emotion and insula function representation. Moreover, the relative weighting of differ-
The present model is related to several contemporary ent information sources according to their reliability in this
frameworks for understanding emotion and self, including process is suggestive of the deployment of precision expec-
prominently those of Damasio [11], Craig [13], and Critch- tations which underlie optimal cue combination in a Bayes-
ley [12]. Each of these sees selfhood as grounded in repre- ian scheme [51]. The engagement of predictive self-models is
sentations of physiological condition, with the AIC further supported by recent evidence showing that percep-
emphasised in some [12,13], but not all [43]. Crucially, tual correlations are not necessary for the RHI; the expec-
none identify emotional states with top-down inference of tation of correlated sensory input is sufficient [52].
the causes of interoceptive signals, as argued here (and as Interestingly, EBO has also been associated with the integ-
recently taken up by others [9]). Rather, they emphasize a rity and activity of the AIC on the basis of lesion data and
continuous, dynamic, but largely bottom-up interoceptive functional neuroimaging in healthy subjects [53].
representational hierarchy that interacts with other Experiments have begun to address the impact of
perceptions to motivate behaviour. Perhaps more closely interoceptive processing on the modulation of EBO in
related is the suggestion that the AIC is involved in error- paradigms like the RHI. One avenue is provided by indi-
based learning of feeling states and uncertainty [15]; here, vidual differences in interoceptive sensitivity (IS), which
the notion of prediction error is expressed in terms of refers to a persons ability to detect their own interocep-
change detection and salience rather than through mech- tive signals, operationalized by heartbeat detection tasks
anisms of predictive coding. Also relevant are models of [54]. Tsakiris and colleagues reported that participants
insular dysfunction during anxiety [16] and psychosis [44] with lower IS are more susceptible to the RHI [55] and to
that hypothesize the existence of interoceptive prediction the modulation of selfother boundaries in response to
errors. However, although these models integrate abun- multisensory stimulation [56,57], possibly reflecting low-
dant evidence compatible with a role for predictive inter- er precision-weighting of interoceptive prediction errors.
oception underlying emotion and self, the core notion of In addition, induction of the RHI leads to decreased
interoceptive inference is not elaborated. temperature [58] and increased histamine reactivity of
the real hand [59], whereas cooling the real hand
The predictive self and the experience of body increases susceptibility to the RHI [60]. Also, threats to
ownership the rubber hand during the RHI evoke enhanced skin
A predictive model of selfhood must extend beyond subjec- conductance responses [61]. These effects are compatible
tive feelings to integrate interoceptive and exteroceptive with descending self-related predictions tuning reference
signals across multiple levels of self-representation. Par- points for autonomic reflexes from the perspective of
ticularly significant is the representation of those parts of active inference.
the world perceived as belonging to ones own body, sup- Two recent studies have addressed directly the role of
porting EBO [45], and which plausibly are closely tied to multisensory integration across interoceptive and extero-
interoception in having the body as a referent. Experi- ceptive domains in shaping EBO. In the first, Suzuki et al.
ments such as the rubber hand illusion (RHI) attest to [19] combined augmented reality with physiological moni-
the plasticity of EBO: stroking of an artificial hand syn- toring to implement a version of the RHI in which a virtual
chronously with a participants real hand, while visual hand changed colour either in-time or out-of-time with an
attention is focused on the artificial hand, leads the par- individuals heartbeat (Figure 3). The authors found that
ticipant to experience the artificial hand as part of her own synchronous cardio-visual feedback enhanced the experi-
body [46]. Similar effects have been described for face ence of ownership of the virtual hand, as measured both
perception [47] and whole-body ownership [48,49]. subjectively by questionnaire and objectively by previously
These manipulations of EBO have been explained by validated measures of proprioceptive drift where the
models of multisensory integration, which propose that latter measures the perceived position of the real (hidden)
conflicts between vision, touch, and proprioception are hand by asking the participant to move a cursor to this
minimized by visual capture of visual and felt (tactile) location. (Note that these two measures do not always
events occurring in peri-personal space, on the basis of correlate [62].) The same setup enabled a replication of
statistical correlations among sensory signals together the standard RHI by contrasting synchronous versus asyn-
with visual dominance [46,50]. This is compatible with chronous tactile-visual feedback. In a third condition,
PC inasmuch as minimization of prediction errors such Suzuki et al. found that real-time remapping of finger
as those induced by multisensory conflicts during the movements to the virtual hand supporting peri-hand
RHI will update the posterior probabilities and, over time, visual-proprioceptive coherence provided strong
can induce changes in self-related priors [22]. Priors reflect- cues for EBO that overshadowed the influence of cardiac
ing high-level representations, such as selfhood and (interoceptive) prediction errors. A second study [20]
569
Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences November 2013, Vol. 17, No. 11

(A) (D) **P < 0.01


Kinect camera *P < 0.05
7
AR marker Head mounted Key:

Propriocepve dri dierence [cm]


n.s. **
display and camera 6
Sync
Async

5
*
4

Physical Virtual 2
hand hand
1
(B)
0
Cardiac sll Cardiac move Tacle

(E) *** P < 0.001


*P < 0.05
3
Ownership Control
Visuo-cardiac feedback Visuo-tacle feedback Propriocepve dri test
2
on the virtual hand by a paint brush * n.s. ***

Subjecve rang
1
(C) Propriocepve Quesonnaire
Inducon dri test (POST) 0
Propriocepve
opriocepve period
dri
i test (PRE) 1

Resng 2 Key:
6 items Sync
period x2 n.s. n.s. n.s.
Async
120s 3
x2 Sll Move Tacle Sll Move Tacle
20s
TRENDS in Cognitive Sciences

Figure 3. An interoceptive rubber-hand illusion. (A) Participants sat facing a desk so that their physical (left) hand was out of sight. A 3D model of the real hand was captured by
Microsoft Kinect and used to generate a real-time virtual hand that was projected into the head-mounted display (HMD) at the location of the augmented-reality (AR) marker.
Subjects wore a front-facing camera connected to the HMD, so they saw the camera image superimposed with the virtual hand. They also wore a pulse-oximeter to measure
heartbeat timings and they used their right hand to make behavioural responses. (B) Cardio-visual feedback (left) was implemented by changing the colour of the virtual hand
from its natural colour towards red and back, over 500 ms either synchronously or asynchronously with the heartbeat. Tactile feedback (middle) was given by a paintbrush,
which was rendered into the AR environment. A proprioceptive drift (PD) test (right), adapted for the AR environment, objectively measured perceived virtual hand position by
implementing a virtual measure and cursor. (C) The experiment consisted of three blocks of four trials each. Each trial consisted of two PD tests flanking an induction period,
during which either cardio-visual or tactile-visual feedback was provided (120 s). Each trial ended with a questionnaire presented in the HMD. (D) PD differences (PDD, post-
induction minus pre-induction) were significantly larger for synchronous versus asynchronous cardio-visual feedback in the cardiac still (without finger movements), but not
the cardiac move condition (with finger movements). PDDs were also significantly larger for synchronous versus asynchronous tactile-visual feedback (tactile condition),
replicating the classical RHI. Each bar shows the across-participant average and standard error. (E) Subjective questionnaire responses that probed experience of ownership
showed the same pattern as PDDs, whereas control questions showed no effect of cardio-visual or tactile-visual synchrony. Adapted from [19].

applied similar cardio-visual feedback to a virtual body as [58,59] when these changes are taken to reflect altered
seen from behind, thus testing the influence of such feed- autonomic control.
back on the full body illusion [48,49]. Consistent with
Suzuki et al.s results, they found that cardio-visual syn- Concluding remarks
chrony increased identification with the virtual body, again This opinion article proposes that emotion and embodied
when measured both objectively and subjectively. selfhood are grounded in active inference of those signals
These data suggest that statistical correlations between most likely to be me across interoceptive and exterocep-
interoceptive (e.g., cardiac) and exteroceptive (e.g., visual) tive domains. In humans, self-related predictive coding
signals can lead to updating of predictive models of self- simultaneously engages multiple levels of self-representa-
related signals through minimization of prediction error, tion, including physiological homeostasis, physical bodily
just as may happen for purely exteroceptive multisensory integrity, morphology and position, and more specula-
conflicts in the classic RHI. Also, if predictive models are tively the metacognitive and narrative I. Subjective
continually probed by control signals that attempt to con- feeling states (emotional experiences) arise from active
firm the currently dominant model via active inference interoceptive inference, extending previous theories based
[21], the framework naturally accommodates the phasic on cognitive appraisal of perceived physiological changes
physiological changes that accompany RHI induction [24] and contemporary frameworks that emphasize
570
Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences November 2013, Vol. 17, No. 11

Box 3. Interoceptive inference and psychopathology


A significant body of work now connects deficits in predictive inference volume with individual interoceptive sensitivity (IS), which in turn
with psychiatric disorders that affect self-representation [6,16,44]. For predicts sensitivity to mood states, including anxiety [12,16]. Indeed,
two decades, comparator models of schizophrenia have suggested anxiety and psychosis have been specifically associated with
that disturbances of selfhood (e.g., delusions of control) reflect mismatches between predicted and actual interoceptive states
problems in distinguishing self-caused from externally-caused changes putatively computed within AIC [16,44]. The finding that low IS
in sensory input [77]. In psychosis, false perceptions (hallucinations) predicts susceptibility to the RHI [55] provides a bridge to under-
and false beliefs (delusions) may arise from reshaping of top-down standing how disorders of body image and ownership may involve
predictions in attempts to suppress aberrant and persistent (exter- disrupted interoceptive inference.
oceptive) prediction errors [78]. This view has been finessed in terms of Dissociative conditions, such as depersonalization and derealisa-
abnormal encoding of the relative precision of priors and sensory tion (DPD), involve disabling disturbances of selfhood, as reflected in
evidence to account for a broad range of psychotic symptoms [79,80]. a persistent sense of unreality (as-if-ness) [85]. These conditions are
Considering interoceptive inference and the AIC as its likely brain associated with alexithymia and a general loss of emotional colour,
basis further enhances the explanatory potential of this framework for suggestive of deficient interoceptive inference and consistent with
psychopathology. Links between perceptions of bodily state and observed hypoactivation of AIC (and ACC bilaterally) in DPD patients
emotional and neuropsychiatric disorders are well established. For when viewing aversive images [86]. By analogy with models of
example, alexithymia (broadly, deficits in emotional awareness) is psychosis [79,80], Seth et al. have suggested that DPD may arise from
associated with failure to engage AIC [81] and with degeneration of imprecise (as opposed to inaccurate) interoceptive predictions, as
AIC and of VENs (Box 2) in the context of fronto-temporal dementia part of a model of conscious presence [6]. The transition from DPD to
[82,83]. Human VENs express proteins linked to schizophrenia full-blown delusion (e.g., Cotards syndrome, in which patients
(notably DISC-1) and VEN density (in the anterior cingulate) has been believe they are dead [87]) may also reflect aberrant high-level
linked to illness duration and completed suicide in psychotic patients inference as the result of attempting to explain away persistent
[84]. Neuroimaging studies have correlated (right) AIC activity and interoceptive prediction errors.

bottom-up elaboration of interoceptive representations of selfhood, is modulated by predictive multisensory inte-


with perception and motivation [11,13,15]. The close inter- gration of precision-weighted interoceptive and exterocep-
play between interoceptive and exteroceptive inference tive signals.
implies that emotional responses are inevitably shaped This framework may have important implications for
by cognitive and exteroceptive context, and that perceptual understanding psychiatric disturbances of selfhood and
scenes that evoke interoceptive predictions will always be emotional awareness. Dysfunctions in interoceptive infer-
affectively coloured. Although the detailed neuroanatomy ence could underlie a range of pathologies, especially those
that underlies interoceptive inference remains to be eluci- that involve dissociative symptoms, such as anxiety
dated, accumulating evidence implicates the AIC as a key (Box 3). A broad role for interoceptive inference is also
comparator mechanism sensitive to interoceptive predic- consistent with recent evidence that shows interoceptive
tion error signals, as informing visceromotor control, and influences on cognition and perception. For example, word
as underpinning conscious access to emotional states (emo- recognition memory is modulated by the timing of visual
tional awareness). A predictive self is further supported by stimuli with respect to cardiac phase under restricted
emerging paradigms that combine virtual/augmented re- attention [63]. Overall, interoceptive inference highlights
ality and physiological monitoring, where the data so far common predictive mechanisms that underlie affect, self,
suggest that the experience of body ownership, a key aspect and perception, emphasizes their integration in shaping
self-related experience, and provides new experimental
Box 4. Questions for future research possibilities for elucidating the underlying processes
(Box 4).
 Can (structurally or functionally) segregated populations of
representation and error units be identified in the interoceptive
Acknowledgements
system? There are some early indications of such segregation in
This work was supported by ERC FP7 project CEEDS (FP7-ICT-258749),
perceptual systems [88].
EPSRC Fellowship EP/G007543/1, and by the Dr Mortimer and Dame
 Do neurotransmitters like dopamine and oxytocin have a role in
Theresa Sackler Foundation, which supports the work of the Sackler
modulating the precision of interoceptive prediction errors [89]?
Centre for Consciousness Science. I am grateful to Sarah Garfinkel, Jakob
How do these roles relate to similar roles in reward processing
Hohwy, Keisuke Suzuki (who also helped prepare Figure 3), Paul
[2]?
Verschure, members of the Sackler Centre, and my reviewers for
 Are VENs engaged in communicating top-down interoceptive
comments which helped improve the manuscript. Special gratitude is
predictions from insular and cingulate cortices to subcortical and
due to Hugo Critchley and Manos Tsakiris for their generous insights
brainstem targets [8]?
which helped shape the ideas presented here.
 What are the functional and effective connectivity patterns that
underlie interoceptive inference and the integration of interocep-
tive and exteroceptive signals relevant to conscious selfhood? References
 What is the relation between predictive models of interoception 1 Clark, A. (2013) Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and
and similar models of agency [90], another central aspect of the future of cognitive science. Behav. Brain Sci. 36, 181204
2 Friston, K.J. (2009) The free-energy principle: a rough guide to the
selfhood?
brain? Trends Cogn. Sci. 13, 293301
 Can predictive models of selfhood accommodate more abstract
3 Lee, T.S. and Mumford, D. (2003) Hierarchical Bayesian inference in
modes of self-experience, such as the narrative self or I that links
episodic memories across time? the visual cortex. J. Opt. Soc. Am. A: Opt. Image Sci. Vis. 20, 14341448
 Can interoceptive feedback provide new avenues for the treat- 4 Hohwy, J. (2013) The Predictive Mind, Oxford University Press
ment of emotional and neuropsychiatric disorders? Might there 5 Craig, A.D. (2002) How do you feel? Interoception: the sense of the
be a role for disrupted interoceptive inference in impairments of physiological condition of the body. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 3, 655666
social emotional behaviour, such as autism? 6 Seth, A.K. et al. (2011) An interoceptive predictive coding model of
conscious presence. Front. Psychol. 2, 395

571
Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences November 2013, Vol. 17, No. 11

7 Seth, A.K. and Critchley, H.D. (2013) Extending predictive processing 40 Valins, S. (1966) Cognitive effects of false heart-rate feedback. J. Pers.
to the body: Emotion as interoceptive inference. Behav. Brain Sci. 36, Soc. Psychol. 4, 400408
227228 41 Gray, M.A. et al. (2007) Modulation of emotional appraisal by false
8 Critchley, H. and Seth, A. (2012) Will studies of macaque insula reveal physiological feedback during fMRI. PLoS ONE 2, e546
the neural mechanisms of self-awareness? Neuron 74, 423426 42 Egner, T. et al. (2008) Neural repetition suppression reflects fulfilled
9 Gu, X. et al. (2013) Anterior insular cortex and emotional awareness. perceptual expectations. Nat. Neurosci. 11, 10041006
J. Comp. Neurol. 521, 33713388 43 Damasio, A. et al. (2013) Persistence of feelings and sentience after
10 James, W. (1894) The physical basis of emotion. Psychol. Rev. 1, bilateral damage of the insula. Cereb. Cortex 23, 833846
516529 44 Palaniyappan, L. and Liddle, P.F. (2011) Does the salience network
11 Damasio, A. (2000) The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in play a cardinal role in psychosis? An emerging hypothesis of insular
the Making of Consciousness, Harvest Books dysfunction. J. Psychiatry Neurosci. 36, 100176
12 Critchley, H.D. et al. (2004) Neural systems supporting interoceptive 45 Blanke, O. (2012) Multisensory brain mechanisms of bodily self-
awareness. Nat. Neurosci. 7, 189195 consciousness. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 13, 556571
13 Craig, A.D. (2009) How do you feel now? The anterior insula and 46 Botvinick, M. and Cohen, J. (1998) Rubber hands feel touch that eyes
human awareness. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 10, 5970 see. Nature 391, 756
14 Damasio, A. and Carvalho, G.B. (2013) The nature of feelings: 47 Sforza, A. et al. (2010) My face in yours: visuo-tactile facial stimulation
evolutionary and neurobiological origins. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 14, 143152 influences sense of identity. Soc. Neurosci. 5, 148162
15 Singer, T. et al. (2009) A common role of insula in feelings, empathy and 48 Lenggenhager, B. et al. (2007) Video ergo sum: manipulating bodily
uncertainty. Trends Cogn. Sci. 13, 334340 self-consciousness. Science 317, 10961099
16 Paulus, M.P. and Stein, M.B. (2006) An insular view of anxiety. Biol. 49 Ehrsson, H.H. (2007) The experimental induction of out-of-body
Psychiatry 60, 383387 experiences. Science 317, 1048
17 Metzinger, T. (2003) Being No-One, MIT Press 50 Makin, T.R. et al. (2008) On the other hand: dummy hands and
18 Northoff, G. and Bermpohl, F. (2004) Cortical midline structures and peripersonal space. Behav. Brain Res. 191, 110
the self. Trends Cogn. Sci. 8, 102107 51 Ernst, M.O. and Banks, M.S. (2002) Humans integrate visual and haptic
19 Suzuki, K. et al. (2013) Multisensory integration across interoceptive and information in a statistically optimal fashion. Nature 415, 429433
exteroceptive domains modulates self-experience in the rubber-hand 52 Ferri, F. et al. (2013) The body beyond the body: expectation of a
illusion. Neuropsychologia http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia. sensory event is enough to induce ownership over a fake hand. Proc.
2013.08.014 R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 280, 20131140
20 Aspell, J.E. et al. (2013) Turning body and self inside out: visualized 53 Karnath, H.O. and Baier, B. (2010) Right insula for our sense of limb
heartbeats alter bodily self-consciousness and tactile perception. ownership and self-awareness of actions. Brain Struct. Funct. 214,
Psychol. Sci. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0956797613498395 411417
21 Friston, K.J. et al. (2010) Action and behavior: a free-energy 54 Schandry, R. (1981) Heart beat perception and emotional experience.
formulation. Biol. Cybern. 102, 227260 Psychophysiology 18, 483488
22 Apps, M.A. and Tsakiris, M. (2013) The free-energy self: a predictive 55 Tsakiris, M. et al. (2011) Just a heartbeat away from ones body:
coding account of self-recognition. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. http:// interoceptive sensitivity predicts malleability of body-representations.
dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2013.01.029 Proc. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 278, 24702476
23 Gendron, M. and Barrett, L.F. (2009) reconstructing the past: a century 56 Tajadura-Jimenez, A. et al. (2012) The person in the mirror: using the
of ideas about emotion in psychology. Emot. Rev. 1, 316339 enfacement illusion to investigate the experiential structure of self-
24 Schachter, S. and Singer, J.E. (1962) Cognitive, social, and physiological identification. Conscious. Cogn. 21, 17251738
determinants of emotional state. Psychol. Rev. 69, 379399 57 Tajadura-Jimenez, A. and Tsakiris, M. (2013) Balancing the Inner and
25 Cantril, H. and Hunt, W.A. (1932) Emotional effects produced by the the Outer Self: Interoceptive Sensitivity Modulates Self-Other
injection of adrenalin. Am. J. Psychol. 44, 300307 Boundaries. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0033171
26 Critchley, H.D. and Harrison, N.A. (2013) Visceral influences on brain 58 Moseley, G.L. et al. (2008) Psychologically induced cooling of a specific
and behavior. Neuron 77, 624638 body part caused by the illusory ownership of an artificial counterpart.
27 Lane, R.D. and Schwartz, G.E. (1987) Levels of emotional awareness: a Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 105, 1316913173
cognitive-developmental theory and its application to psychopathology. 59 Barnsley, N. et al. (2011) The rubber hand illusion increases histamine
Am. J. Psychiatry 144, 133143 reactivity in the real arm. Curr. Biol. 21, R945R946
28 Dolan, R.J. (2002) Emotion, cognition, and behavior. Science 298, 60 Kammers, M.P. et al. (2011) Feeling numb: temperature, but not thermal
11911194 pain, modulates feeling of body ownership. Neuropsychologia 49,
29 Adams, R.A. et al. (2013) Predictions not commands: active inference in 13161321
the motor system. Brain Struct. Funct. 218, 611643 61 Armel, K.C. and Ramachandran, V.S. (2003) Projecting sensations to
30 Deen, B. et al. (2011) Three systems of insular functional connectivity external objects: evidence from skin conductance response. Proc. R.
identified with cluster analysis. Cereb. Cortex 21, 14981506 Soc. B Biol. Sci. 270, 14991506
31 Ploghaus, A. et al. (1999) Dissociating pain from its anticipation in the 62 Rohde, M. et al. (2011) The Rubber Hand Illusion: feeling of
human brain. Science 284, 19791981 ownership and proprioceptive drift do not go hand in hand. PLoS
32 Lovero, K.L. et al. (2009) Anterior insular cortex anticipates impending ONE 6, e21659
stimulus significance. Neuroimage 45, 976983 63 Garfinkel, S.N. et al. (2013) What the heart forgets: cardiac timing
33 Seymour, B. et al. (2004) Temporal difference models describe higher- influences memory for words and is modulated by metacognition and
order learning in humans. Nature 429, 664667 interoceptive sensitivity. Psychophysiology 50, 505512
34 Preuschoff, K. et al. (2008) Human insula activation reflects risk 64 Blanke, O. and Metzinger, T. (2009) Full-body illusions and minimal
prediction errors as well as risk. J. Neurosci. 28, 27452752 phenomenal selfhood. Trends Cogn. Sci. 13, 713
35 Holle, H. et al. (2012) Neural basis of contagious itch and why 65 Friston, K.J. (2005) A theory of cortical responses. Philos. Trans.
some people are more prone to it. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 109, R. Soc. Lond. B: Biol. Sci. 360, 815836
1981619821 66 Dayan, P. et al. (1995) The Helmholtz machine. Neural Comput. 7,
36 Singer, T. et al. (2004) Empathy for pain involves the affective but not 889904
sensory components of pain. Science 303, 11571162 67 Hinton, G.E. and Dayan, P. (1996) Varieties of Helmholtz Machine.
37 Xiang, T. et al. (2013) Computational substrates of norms and their Neural Netw. 9, 13851403
violations during social exchange. J. Neurosci. 33, 10991108 68 Clark, A. (2012) Dreaming the whole cat: generative models, predictive
38 Frith, C.D. and Frith, U. (2012) Mechanisms of social cognition. Annu. processing, and the enactivist conception of perceptual experience.
Rev. Psychol. 63, 287313 Mind 121, 753771
39 Wolpert, D.M. et al. (2003) A unifying computational framework for 69 Cechetto, D.F. and Saper, C.B. (1987) Evidence for a viscerotopic
motor control and social interaction. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. sensory representation in the cortex and thalamus in the rat.
B: Biol. Sci. 358, 593602 J. Comp. Neurol. 262, 2745

572
Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences November 2013, Vol. 17, No. 11

70 Medford, N. and Critchley, H.D. (2010) Conjoint activity of anterior 80 Synofzik, M. et al. (2010) Misattributions of agency in schizophrenia
insular and anterior cingulate cortex: awareness and response. Brain are based on imprecise predictions about the sensory consequences of
Struct. Funct. 214, 535549 ones actions. Brain 133, 262271
71 Menon, V. and Uddin, L.Q. (2010) Saliency, switching, attention and 81 Silani, G. et al. (2008) Levels of emotional awareness and autism: an
control: a network model of insula function. Brain Struct. Funct. 214, fMRI study. Soc. Neurosci. 3, 97112
655667 82 Seeley, W.W. (2010) Anterior insula degeneration in frontotemporal
72 Allman, J.M. et al. (2010) The von Economo neurons in frontoinsular dementia. Brain Struct. Funct. 214, 465475
and anterior cingulate cortex in great apes and humans. Brain Struct. 83 Kim, E.J. et al. (2012) Selective frontoinsular von Economo neuron and
Funct. 214, 495517 fork cell loss in early behavioral variant frontotemporal dementia.
73 Evrard, H.C. et al. (2012) Von economo neurons in the anterior insula of Cereb. Cortex 22, 251259
the macaque monkey. Neuron 74, 482489 84 Allman, J.M. et al. (2011) The von Economo neurons in the
74 Khalsa, S.S. et al. (2009) The pathways of interoceptive awareness. frontoinsular and anterior cingulate cortex. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci.
Nat. Neurosci. 12, 14941496 1225, 5971
75 Craig, A.D. (2011) Significance of the insula for the evolution of 85 Sierra, M. and David, A.S. (2011) Depersonalization: a selective
human awareness of feelings from the body. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. impairment of self-awareness. Conscious. Cogn. 20, 99108
1225, 7282 86 Phillips, M.L. et al. (2001) Depersonalization disorder: thinking
76 Harrison, N.A. et al. (2010) The embodiment of emotional feelings in without feeling. Psychiatry Res. 108, 145160
the brain. J. Neurosci. 30, 1287812884 87 Young, A.W. and Leafhead, K.M. (1996) Betwixt life and death: case
77 Frith, C. (2011) Explaining delusions of control: the comparator model studies of the Cotard delusion. In Method in Madness (Halligan, P.W.
20 years on. Conscious. Cogn. 21, 5254 and Marshall, J.C., eds), Psychology Press
78 Fletcher, P.C. and Frith, C.D. (2009) Perceiving is believing: a 88 Keller, G.B. et al. (2012) Sensorimotor mismatch signals in primary
Bayesian approach to explaining the positive symptoms of visual cortex of the behaving mouse. Neuron 74, 809815
schizophrenia. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 10, 4858 89 Friston, K.J. (2013) The fantastic organ. Brain 136, 13281332
79 Adams, R.A. et al. (2013) The computational anatomy of psychosis. 90 Friston, K. (2012) Prediction, perception and agency. Int.
Front. Psychiatry 4, 47 J. Psychophysiol. 83, 248252

573

También podría gustarte