Está en la página 1de 5

Alexander Pope's "Essay on Criticism": An Introduction

Pope's "Essay on Criticism" is a didactic poem in heroic couplets, begun, perhaps, as early as
1705, and published, anonymously, in 1711. The poetic essay was a relatively new genre, and
the "Essay" itself was Pope's most ambitious work to that time. It was in part an attempt on
Pope's part to identify and refine his own positions as poet and critic, and his response to an
ongoing critical debate which centered on the question of whether poetry should be "natural"
or written according to predetermined "artificial" rules inherited from the classical past.

The poem commences with a discussion of the rules of taste which ought to govern poetry,
and which enable a critic to make sound critical judgements. In it Pope comments, too, upon
the authority which ought properly to be accorded to the classical authors who dealt with the
subject; and concludes (in an apparent attempt to reconcile the opinions of the advocates and
opponents of rules) that the rules of the ancients are in fact identical with the rules of Nature:
poetry and painting, that is, like religion and morality, actually reflect natural law. The "Essay
on Criticism," then, is deliberately ambiguous: Pope seems, on the one hand, to admit that
rules are necessary for the production of and criticism of poetry, but he also notes the
existence of mysterious, apparently irrational qualities--"Nameless Graces," identified by
terms such as "Happiness" and "Lucky Licence"--with which Nature is endowed, and which
permit the true poetic genius, possessed of adequate "taste," to appear to transcend those same
rules. The critic, of course, if he is to appreciate that genius, must possess similar gifts. True
Art, in other words, imitates Nature, and Nature tolerates and indeed encourages felicitous
irregularities which are in reality (because Nature and the physical universe are creations of
God) aspects of the divine order of things which is eternally beyond human comprehension.
Only God, the infinite intellect, the purely rational being, can appreciate the harmony of the
universe, but the intelligent and educated critic can appreciate poetic harmonies which echo
those in nature. Because his intellect and his reason are limited, however, and because his
opinions are inevitably subjective, he finds it helpful or necessary to employ rules which are
interpretations of the ancient principles of nature to guide him--though he should never be
totally dependent upon them. We should note, in passing, that in "The Essay on Criticism"
Pope is frequently concerned with "wit"--the word occurs once, on average, in every sixteen
lines of the poem. What does he mean by it?

Pope then proceeds to discuss the laws by which a critic should be guided--insisting, as any
good poet would, that critics exist to serve poets, not to attack them. He then provides, by way
of example, instances of critics who had erred in one fashion or another. What, in Pope's
opinion (here as elsewhere in his work) is the deadliest critical sin--a sin which is itself a
reflection of a greater sin? All of his erring critics, each in their own way, betray the same
fatal flaw.

The final section of the poem discusses the moral qualities and virtues inherent in the ideal
critic, who is also the ideal man--and who, Pope laments, no longer exists in the degenerate
world of the early eighteenth century.
Domain: Literature. Genre: Poem, Criticism, Essay, Satire, Treatise. Country: England,
Britain, Europe.

An Essay on Criticism was first published, anonymously, on 15 May 1711. Pope began
writing the poem, however, including drafting and revising it, some two or three years earlier
when he was twenty or twenty one years old. It is, in several ways, a young man's poem,
albeit an exceptional young man's: it is precocious in its learning; dazzling in the range and
inventiveness of its imagery; injunctive in much of its syntax; and remarkably assured in the
breadth of material it encompasses.

An Essay on Criticism is primarily didactic, conducted according to a broadly argumentative


structure, although it contains more than a passing touch of Pope's burgeoning, satiric instinct.
Pope described the poem, in a letter to his friend John Caryll, written on 19 July 1711, as a
treatise ... which not one gentleman in three score, even of a liberal education, can
understand. What Pope seems to have meant by this is that the poem is more densely woven
and subtly argued than appears at first glance. It is not a treatise, however, that offers new
critical insights or positions. It is, rather, an attempt to mediate between a wide range of
traditional and contemporary critical thought and arrive at an acceptable synthesis of the two.
The poem is what its title says it is, an essai, or, as Pope calls it towards the end of the
poem, a short Excursion (738), into a much debated and contentious, topical subject: the
role and function of criticism.

In An Essay on Criticism Pope attempts to reconcile the contemporary dispute between the
proponents of ancient and modern learning. Then, as now, Critic Learning flourished most in
France (712). French critics had taken the lead in establishing a new aesthetics, and treatises
by Bouhours, Boileau, Rapin, Le Bossu and Dacier, dealing with such matters as the imitation
of nature and the importance of the rules, dominated the last quarter of the seventeenth
century. Pope was widely read in this modern criticism, as well, of course, as in the
ancient criticism that preceded it, especially in Aristotle, Horace, Quintilian and Longinus.
In An Essay on Criticism he ranges broadly over this extensive body of writing, although
never with the methodical regularity many of the moderns displayed, and attempts to come
up with an authoritative distillation of the differing critical positions.

The poem is the nearest thing in eighteenth-century, English writing to what might be called a
neo-classical manifesto, although it is never as categorically expounded as the term implies. It
comes closer, perhaps, to being a handbook, or guide, to the critic's and poet's art, very much
in the style of Horace's Ars Poetica, or, to take the English models with which the young Pope
was especially familiar, the Earl of Roscommon's translation of Horace, The Art Of Poetry,
(1680), and John Sheffield's (the Duke of Buckingham's) Essay On Poetry, (1682). It is a

http://www.litencyc.com/php/sworks.php?rec=true&UID=5312

An Outline of Pope's "Essay on Criticism"

Part 1. This section offers general principles of good criticism (and of poetry--since
criticism for Pope means determining the merit of a work rather than its meaning,
understanding the principles of good criticism means understanding the rules for
good poetry and vice versa).
The problem: "'Tis with our judgments as our watches, none/ Go just alike, yet
each believes his own." Judgments are partial, and true taste is as rare as true
genius (9-35). Some critics go astray through false learning, others through
envy of wit (19-45). Self-awareness is therefore a crucial quality for a critic (46-
67): "Be sure yourself and your own reach you know."
First solution: "First follow Nature" (68-87). (Nature here means something like
"the universe as God created it" or "that which is permanently true.")
Second solution: learn the "rules of old," i.e. the precepts of poetry and
criticism set down by the classical Greek and Roman authors or deducible
from their literature (88-140). Take care, however, not to follow the rules
slavishly, but rather "know well each ancient's proper character," especially
Homer.
One reason to be flexible in applying the rules: there are "beauties yet no
precepts can declare." Great writers can break the rules successfully (141-
180). Modern poets should take care, however, that if they break a rule they
should "ne'er transgress its end" (161-169).

Part 2. This section identifies the main flaws a critic is prone to, and therefore the
greatest obstacles to good criticism.

The biggest pitfall, in criticism as in just about everything else: pride (201-214).
Flaw #2: "little learning" (215-232). A little learning makes critics susceptible to
pride, by making them think they know more than they do. (Pope is not
praising ignorance here; the cure for the pride of little learning is more
learning, which teaches the scholar how little he or she knows.)
#3: "a love to parts"--i.e. emphasizing one aspect of a poem at the expense of
all others (233-383). A critic SHOULD, instead, "read each work of wit/With the
same spirit that its author writ"; "Survey the whole" and "regard the writer's
end" (233-252).
o an absurd example of "a love to parts": for Don Quixote, a poem is no
good unless it has a combat in it (267-284).
o part #1: conceit (elaborate, clever tropes) (289-304).
o part #2: eloquence of language (305-337), as opposed to the ideas the
language is supposed to express. One example: archaic language
(324-336).
o part #3: "numbers," i.e. meter (337-384). Included in the section is a
dazzling display of metrical craft--note how the lines exemplify what
they're talking about.
#4: love of extremes (384-393)
#5: liking only "one small sect," e.g. foreign writers, British author, ancients, or
moderns, as opposed to approving of merit wherever it is found (394-407).
#6:judging authors according to the opinions of others rather than the merit of
the work (408-424). E.g.:
o judging the name rather than the work (412-413).
o worst case: judging the work on the basis of social rank (414-424).
#7: conversely, prizing novelty above everything else (424-451).
#8: valuing only those works which agree with one's own point of view, are
written by member of one's own party, are written by friends, etc. (452-473).
Envy plays a big part here, says Pope.
arising from the above, some premises: "Be thou the first true merit to defend,"
even though we cannot expect modern writers to endure as the ancients did
(474-493).; don't let yourself succumb to envy (494-525). Be generous: "To err
is human, to forgive divine."
But DO scourge "provoking crimes" such as obscenity and blasphemy (526-
555). Here too, however, one must take care not to "mistake an author into
vice" (556-559).

http://titan.iwu.edu/~wchapman/britpoet/popeessay.html

Alexander Pope
by Walter Jackson Bate

In the Essay on Criticism (1711), written in 1709 when he was hardly twenty-one, Pope was
trying to write a poetical essay which would hold the same important place in English that
Boileau's Art Potique (1674) was holding in French criticism. If it did not quite attain this
position, the reason is not that Pope's essay is inferior to Boileau's. It is simply that English
writers of any period, including the age of Pope, have a way of refusing to form schools and
follow manifestoes. Still, Pope's Essay on Criticism is not only the last but perhaps the most
rewarding of the important critical essays in verse modeled on Horace's Art of Poetry. It
draws upon the previous verse-essays of Horace, Vida, and Boileau, as well as those of two
minor Restoration writers, the Earls of Mulgrave and Roscommon. It also draws upon
precepts from the Roman Quintilian and the French critics, Rapin and Le Bossu. Above all, its
general tone is kept comparatively liberal and flexible by the influence of Dryden, and, to
some extent, of Longinus. The background is broad. This may partly explain why the Essay
on Criticism is more comprehensive in what it covers than any of the other Horatian verse-
essays, including that of Boileau. It also quite equals Boileau in edge of style, and it surpasses
him in compactness.

The Essay on Criticism is more profitably introduced by a topical summary of its themes than
by an analysis of its premises. For its premises and aims are those of the entire neoclassic
tradition. And the poem itself is a statement or summary of them rather than an individual
argument or analysis. The essay may be described as falling into three parts, with the
following subdivisions:

I. General qualities needed by the critic (1-200):


A. Awareness of his own limitations (46-67).
B. Knowledge of Nature in its general forms (68-87).
1. Nature defined (70-79).
2. Need of both wit and judgment to conceive it (80-87).
C. Imitation of the Ancients, and the use of rules (88-200).
1. Value of ancient poetry and criticism as models (88-103).
2. Censure of slavish imitation and codified rules (104-117).
3. Need to study the general aims and qualities of the Ancients (118-140).
4. Exceptions to the rules (141-168).
II. Particular laws for the critic (201-559):
Digression on the need for humility (201-232).
A. Consider the work as a total unit (233-252).
B. Seek the author's aim (253-266).
C. Examples of false critics who mistake the part for the whole (267-383).
1. The pedant who forgets the end and judges by rules (267-288).
2. The critic who judges by imagery and metaphor alone (289-304).
3. The rhetorician who judges by the pomp and color of the diction (305-336).
4. Critics who judge by versification only (337-343).
Pope's digression to exemplify "representative meter" (344-383).
D. Need for tolerance and for aloofness from extremes of fashion and personal
mood (384-559).
1. The fashionable critic: the cults, as ends in themselves, of the foreign (398-
405), the new (406-423), and the esoteric (424-451).
2. Personal subjectivity and its pitfalls (452-559).
III. The ideal character of the critic (560-744):
Qualities needed: integrity (562-565), modesty (566-571), tact (572-577),
A.
courage (578-583).
B. Their opposites (584-630).
C. Concluding eulogy of ancient critics as models (643-744).

The intention of this outline is simply to clarify the topics discussed by Pope. It is by no
means intended to attribute an argumentative or reasoned order to the poem. For as Johnson
said of Warburton's attempt to discover the order or design of the Essay on Criticism:

Almost every poem, consisting of precepts, is so far arbitrary and immethodical, that
many of the paragraphs may change place with no apparent inconvenience; for of two
and more positions, depending upon some remote or general principle, there is seldom
any cogent reason
http://www.ourcivilisation.com/smartboard/shop/batewj/pope.htm

exposition of prosodic theory

Early in the 18th century, Pope affirmed, in his Essay on Criticism (1711), the classic doctrine
of imitation. Prosody was to be more nearly onomatopoetic; the movement of sound and
metre should represent the actions they carry:'Tis not enough no harshness gives offence,
The sound must seem an Echo to the sense:
Soft is the strain when Zephyr gently...

Essay on Criticsm:
- didactic poem in heroic couplets
It begins with an exposition of the rules of taste and the authority to be attributed to the
ancient writers on the subject. The laws by which a critic should be guided are then discussed,
and instances are given of critics who have departed from them. The work is remarkable as
having been written when Pope was only 21.

También podría gustarte