Está en la página 1de 18

European Journal of Social Theory http://est.sagepub.

com/

A common world? Arendt, Castoriadis and political creation


Ingerid S. Straume European Journal of Social Theory 2012 15: 367 originally published online 26 March 2012 DOI: 10.1177/1368431012440870 The online version of this article can be found at: http://est.sagepub.com/content/15/3/367

Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com

Additional services and information for European Journal of Social Theory can be found at: Email Alerts: http://est.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://est.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Citations: http://est.sagepub.com/content/15/3/367.refs.html

>> Version of Record - Jul 9, 2012 OnlineFirst Version of Record - Mar 26, 2012 What is This?

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

Article
European Journal of Social Theory 15(3) 367383 The Author(s) 2012 Reprints and permission: sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/1368431012440870 est.sagepub.com

A common world? Arendt, Castoriadis and political creation


Ingerid S. Straume University of Oslo, Norway

Abstract Among the many parallels between Hannah Arendt and Cornelius Castoriadis is their shared interest in the kind of politics that is characteristic of the council movements, revolutionary moments and the political democracy of ancient Greece. This article seeks to elucidate how the two thinkers fill out and complement each others thought, with special attention to political creationan ambiguous theme in Arendts thought. While critical of the notion of making in the political field, Arendt also emphasizes the importance of building institutions. To take this seriously means that her analyses of the nature of politics must be modified and, in this respect, Castoriadiss understanding of politics as institution-building can serve as a guideline. However, Arendts concept of plurality in the public sphere represents a level of political analysis that is underdeveloped in the work of Castoriadis. Taken together, their thought highlights many important aspects of political creation in a radical sense. Keywords Arendt, castoriadis, creation, politics, revolutionary movements Hannah Arendt and Cornelius Castoriadis, arguably two of the most original thinkers of the 20th century, shared a deep interest in political action and the possibility for something new to appear in the sphere of politics. The parallels in their work become all the more intriguing in view of the difficulties with which their respective oeuvres combine with those of other thinkers.1 Owing to their idiosyncrasies, attempts to discuss their arguments tend to become enveloped in their respective philosophical universes. Of

Corresponding author: Ingerid S. Straume, University of Oslo, University of Oslo Library, PO Box 1009 Blindern, 0315 Oslo, Norway Email: ingerid.straume@ub.uio.no

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

368

European Journal of Social Theory 15(3)

course, this may not have been entirely to their dismay, as both were deeply critical towards traditional ways of doing philosophy (as exemplified by Plato), and, while claiming not to be theory builders, they both, more or less explicitly, asserted their own (anti-foundationalist) alternatives. The challenges in the case of Hannah Arendt are connected to style, as well as substance. Her work is phenomenological at times, categorical at others; her style of prose essayistic rather than systematic. She would sometimes pursue her themes longer than what would seem necessary or productive, and cared little whether she was correctly understood (Canovan, 1994: 3). For these, and other, reasons, she is often misunderstood (Canovan, 1994; Pitkin, 1998). In the case of Castoriadis, the challenges are mostly connected to his mode of philosophizing, termed elucidation. Elucidation can be contrasted to definition aimed at determinacy: where the latter strives toward pinpointing a phenomenon in a more or less unequivocal manner, elucidation means to explore the way phenomena operate in the world in their various modes of existence (Castoriadis, 1984, 1987; Whitebook, 1985). The ontological premise is that the social reality is not describable in an exhaustive manner; there is always an undetermined surplus of meaning. Thus, elucidation echoes the magmatic nature of thought and of the social-historical. When Castoriadis works out his thought in chains of (often self-made) concepts, where one is elucidated, explained and understood through the introduction of another, this poses a considerable challenge to those who seek to present Castoriadiss work and discuss it in a systematicconceptually distinctway. There are also important biographical parallels between Arendt and Castoriadis. Both spent their adult life in exile, which meant the loss not only of a mother tongue as a working language, but also a referential world wherein thoughts can be expressed. For large parts of their lives, both were more engaged in the public sphere than in mainstream academia. There are, of course, also major differences between the two thinkers, as we shall see. The task of the present essay is not, however, to make comparisons per se, but rather to highlight a specific theme where Arendt and Castoriadis complement each other, but where productive tensions also lie; namely, the nature of political creation. A guiding idea of this article is to show how the weaker points of one thinker can be used to elucidate the strengths of the other. In the following sections I outline what politics means for Arendt and Castoriadis respectively. In my discussion I am particularly interested in the challenges they pose for each other, such as whether Arendts critique of the use of the notion of poiesis (making) in political matters applies to Castoriadiss project of autonomy and, conversely, whether the latter can inform Arendts stark divisions between the human spheres of activity, which has been strongly criticized. I also discuss Arendts concept of plurality and argue that it represents a missing level in Castoriadiss philosophy. To round off, I turn to the contemporary global scene, with its on-going social revolts and financial and political crises, and consider in what sense the thought of Arendt and Castoriadis can elucidate these socio-political phenomena.

Politics and poiesis


There is no doubt that Castoriadis has studied the works of Hannah Arendt, whereas it is unlikely that Arendt ever read Castoriadis.2 A common ground is their deep fascination

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

Straume

369

for the notion of politics that first emerged with the twin birth of politics and philosophy around the 5th century BCE (Arendt, 1989; Castoriadis, 1991, 1997a). While emphasizing different aspects of the political impulses of the Athenian polis, both made active use of the Greek case to further their own political thought. A further parallel is their active engagement with the political events of their time, which crystallized in their respective political analyses of the USSR, totalitarianism, revolutions, the Cold War and the growth of modern bureaucracy. A special status was given to various historical initiatives of self-organization, such as the Hungarian workers councils, which inspired both of them (Arendt, 1990; Castoriadis, 1988). Like the Greek polis, they saw the councils as rare instances of genuine politics, which, for Castoriadis, would be manifestations of the project of autonomy, while for Arendt they signified moments of power and spontaneous action. What is the nature of the politics that was born in ancient Greece and reborn in modern revolutionary moments, such as Hungary in 1956? One central characteristic is the communicative aspects of politics: public discussion, questioning, deliberation and debate. But a more distinctive and important feature is self-organization: when people take it upon themselves to create institutions that regulate their own active participation in the running of society. The terminology varies, but Castoriadis and Arendt are fascinated by similar phenomena. What Arendt calls politics proper (as well as genuine or authentic politics), Castoriadis calls true politics, or just politics (la politique). Castoriadis sees politics as distinct from the political (le politique), which refers to the political field, such as institutions of explicit and regulative power. In mainstream political theory, however, it is the latter notion that is most often elaborated under the term of politics.3 For both thinkers, failing to distinguish between the political field and politics proper means to cover up the radical potential of politics, where practices of freedom, action, spontaneity (Arendt) and creativity (Castoriadis) can take place. In the case of Greece, where politics emerged for the first time, general political participation was made possible by the creation of the public sphere, a point elucidated by Arendt (1989) and acclaimed by Castoriadis (1991: 112). A vital public sphere is characterized by on-going discussion of questions of collective interest. This shared notion of politics is underpinned by what Castoriadis (1987) calls an ontology of doing and Arendt calls the active life: vita activa.4 They reject the widespread tendency to regard politics as a defined set of practices that can be organized and managed in a bureaucratic fashion once the proper institutions are in place. Representative democracy, for example, is seen to have very little political potential. For Arendt and Castoriadis, politics is a delicate matter that needs to be continually exercised and kept alive through vital public discussion, deliberation and dissent. Above all, politics signifies freedom. Arendt argues that: tre of politics is freedom, and its field of experience is action (2006a: The raison de 145), while Castoriadis tells us that The objective of politics is not happiness but freedom (1997b: 5). Exactly because it is an embodiment of freedom, however, politics is one of the first things to disappear from a society when, for instance, its inhabitants stop caring about their common world or cease to question societys institutions, laws and foundations (Arendt, 2004; Castoriadis, 1991). So far, I have presented the common ground between Castoriadis and Arendt in their respective views on politics. It is true that the resemblances are striking, but there are also

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

370

European Journal of Social Theory 15(3)

great differences, some of which concern the very nature of politics itself. When the subject is probed further, the question of political praxis becomes crucial. As we will see, Castoriadiss notion of political doing and Arendts understanding of action are not reducible to each other, but steer the discussion in rather different directions. This becomes clear when we consider the concept of political creation: the process whereby a specific society is createdor creates itselfwith its specific institutions, norms and significations. If we take political creation to mean a politics that aims at making political institutions, the notion becomes rather problematic for Arendt, while Castoriadiss politics is quite attached to such ideas, especially in his emphasis of the project of autonomy. In order to explore these differences, we will make a brief visit to ancient Greece. In Greece, the co-birth of politics and philosophy made possible the creation of democracy, which, for Castoriadis, is an embodiment of the project of autonomy. Autonomy, in short, means to posit ones own laws. But whereas all societiesincluding heteronomous societiesdo posit their own laws, only autonomous societies do this in an explicit, conscious way. According to Castoriadis, the Greeks were the first to realize that their laws were entirely their own creation, with no external foundations. The autonomy in question here is not of the Kantian or liberal kind, that is individual-based independence from others, but a participatory, collective activity: a strong version of what in contemporary parlance is called active citizenship. But there is more: autonomy is always individual and collective; it cannot be practiced by individuals unless it is collectively instituted, which means that there is a collective awareness that society posits and creates its own laws. Autonomy is, in one of many formulations, the project that aims . . . at bringing light to societys instituting power and at rendering it explicit in reflection (Castoriadis, 1991: 174). Autonomy is political freedom, but it is also necessarily self-limiting, as there are no external limitations to the project of autonomy. It is important for Castoriadis to conceptualize societys capacity to create. Society here consists of two aspects: that which creates itself as society, instituting society and that which is created in each case, instituted society. As Castoriadis tells us, Society is self-creation. That which creates society and history is the instituting society, as opposed to the instituted society (1991: 84). Autonomy means to be aware of this relationship, while heteronomy means to cover it up. Politics is of the utmost importance here. It means not only to debate, deliberate and question the instituted laws and norms, but, more importantly, to create new laws and institutions; in other words, effective and creative self-rule (autogestion). Thus, political activity concerns the institution of society itself: Politics is the lucid and reflective collective activity that aims at the overall institution of society. It pertains to everything in society that is participable and shareable (Castoriadis, 1991: 169). Within the project of autonomy, political doing is, for Castoriadis, the creation of societal forms, while in philosophical terms, doing (faire) is an alternative to repetition, reconstruction and interpretation, which Castoriadis (1987) saw as expressions of a reductionist ontology that regarded being as being-determined and hence not creative.5 Thus, genuine politics for Castoriadisdemocratic politicsis about the conscious and deliberate, collective creation of institutions. Hannah Arendt took a different approach to the problem of determinism (or more fundamentally, foundationalism) with her concept of actionan approach that seems to be at odds with

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

Straume

371

Castoriadis. In The Human Condition, she sets forth a strong critique of the modern idea that human beings make their history, which was brought to its full expression with Marx, but whose origin lies with Platos political theory:
Marxs dictum [in Capital] that violence is the midwife of every old society pregnant with a new one, that is, of all change in history and politics, only sums up the conviction of the whole modern age and draws the consequences of its innermost conviction that history is made by men as nature is made by God (Arendt, 1989: 228).

According to Arendt, the idea that history is made rests on a conflation of action/ praxis with fabrication/poiesis, or, rather, the occultation of action altogether: an operation that has set its mark on the whole terminology of political theory and political thought that indeed makes it almost impossible to discuss these matters [politics and history] without using the category of means and ends and thinking in terms of instrumentality (Arendt, 1989: 229). To understand the depth of her argumentwhich underpins a comprehensive critique of the organization of modern societies, the social sciences and politicaladministrative thoughtwe need to briefly recapitulate her theory of labour, work and action as the three modes of the vita activa, the active life, which, she claims, were operative in the polis of ancient Greece.6 For Arendt (1989), the most primitive of the three activities is labour. She understands labour as the activity of the life processes (bios), the everyday tasks, such as the production and consumption of food, that can neither be abandoned nor terminated, but which repeat themselves, day after day, year after year, by the cyclical logic of necessity. These processes and activities are of no (political) interest for Arendt: they belong to the oikos, the private sphere, that is the household and the economy. The next activity is work, which is concerned with making and fabricating objects, such as more or less durable artefacts. The guiding principle of fabrication is the meansend category mentioned above. The process of fabrication starts from the idea of the end product and means are chosen as the best way to realize it. Fabrication always implies a certain violence, a manipulative use of the material out of which the product is fabricated. Its logic is poiesis, which, for Arendt, characterizes the making of a world of objects and things, a human artifice which constitutes a common world for inhabiting and living together. This common world is necessary for the exercise of politics, but it is not in itself political. This isolation of poiesis from political action reflects one of her most disputed ideas: her critique of bringing the social question into politics.7 For Arendt (1989, 1990), social matters, such as material needs and poverty, were destructive to political lifethey should be regarded as technical matters (matters of making, fabrication) and kept outside of politics proper (Pitkin, 1998; Villa, 1996). I will return to this below. The third activitywhich needs a public space to occuris what Arendt calls action. The term denotes human affairs that have no ends, nor are they mere (life) processes. Action designates spontaneity, coming together, beginningbut beginnings whose ends or products are unforeseeable and therefore not really ends or products at all. The main activity of action is speech and its logic is spontaneity. Action is meaningful in itself and, as such, the only activity that can make human beings into unique and

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

372

European Journal of Social Theory 15(3)

distinct beings: In man, otherness, which he shares with everything that is, and distinctness, which he shares with everything alive, become uniqueness. Speech and action reveal this uniqueness (Arendt, 1989: 176). The general meaning of action is to begin, to set something into motion, but in Arendts sense action is not the beginning of something, it is the beginning of somebody, who is a beginner himself (Arendt, 1989: 177). In fact, Arendt only speaks of action in connection with a who, the doer or actor who comes forth as a speaker of words: though his deed can be perceived in its brute physical appearance without verbal accompaniment, it becomes relevant only through the spoken word in which he identifies himself as the actor, announcing what he does, has done, and intends to do. For [i]n acting and speaking, men show who they are, reveal actively their unique personal identities and thus make their appearance in the human world (Arendt, 1989: 179). This disclosure of who, in contradistinction to what someone is, is of great political importance to Arendt, who is deeply critical of political regimes and theories that are only able to conceptualize anonymous (life) processes, the extreme case being totalitarianism, but also strongly represented in Marxism.8 According to Arendt, the Marxian idea of history as mere realization of historical laws, or politics understood as the making or fabrication of new societal forms, conflates the politically important distinctions between labour, work and action. As a result, there is an occultation of the most fragile of the three activities, action: the only activity whereby agents become humanized as unique individuals (or persons). On Arendts account, such veiling of the actor characterizes the construction of all utopias and political theories that are supposed to be implemented, administered and realized on the basis of principles thought out in advance. Such thoughts have been among the most effective vehicles to conserve and develop a tradition of political thinking in which, consciously or unconsciously, the concept of action was interpreted in terms of making and fabrication (Arendt, 1989: 228). And even though other readings of Marx are valid, and he certainly inherits a lot of these problems from Hegel (as Arendt also points out, cf. Forti, 2006), Marxs thought does offer itself as a prime example of such instrumentalism, especially the mainstream Marxism that was prevalent in many Western countries around the 1950s, when The Human Condition was written. Not only did this type of Marxism contain an end product, classless society, but it aimed at figuring out (by logical deduction) the necessary means to achieve this state, some of which were violent. Or perhaps more precisely, any means that were seen to approach the end state were deemed necessary, and hencefor Marxism-Leninism at leastlogical. Besides Arendts rejection of an instrumentalism that clearly rules out all deliberation, problematization and questioning in the strong sense, there is also another reason why it is so urgent for Arendt to conceptualize politics as a non-instrumental activity. When we speak and act, and thus show who we are, this always implies speaking, acting and appearing for someone else; someone who is different from oneself. A defining condition for action, therefore, is what Arendt calls plurality, meaning that individuals that are different from each other relate to each other in a free and acknowledging manner. This does not necessarily imply that they agree, but rather, and more importantly, that they make themselves recognized as equals. Their uniqueness and distinctness makes individuals relate to each other as subjects that form a common world. In one of her most quoted phrases, Arendt notes that: The hope for man in his singularity lay

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

Straume

373

in the fact that not man but men inhabit the earth and form a world between them (1990: 175). For Arendt, the frailty of singular individuals is contained by worldly relationships and institutions. Closely related to the human condition of plurality is the notion of human power, which, for Arendt, is a collective matter, based on plurality. [P]ower comes into being only if and when men join themselves together for the purpose of action, and it will disappear when, for whatever reason, they will disperse and desert one another (Arendt, 1990: 175). And when actions are set into motion, the condition of plurality makes the results of action unforeseeable, as acts work upon acts in the complex web of beginners. Thus, to eradicate plurality also means to veil or forget history and temporality (Forti, 2006). Politics, for Arendt, represents contingency, finitude, temporality, plurality and difference (Forti, 2006: 116). It is worldly, as opposed to philosophical or theoretical. In The Human Condition especially, she sees authentic politics as the antithesis to poiesis, while stressing the emergence of the actor who appears to others and reveals who he is. Thus, Arendt frames the discussion in an expressivist, phenomenological and agentoriented notion of political action, where the point of the activity is not to create something, but rather to stand out as unique individuals for each other. Thus, when describing and judging political matters, Arendt tends to use aesthetic, rather than moral, arguments (Kateb, 2006: 140ff). Arendts great achievement is to elucidate the importance of an autonomous public sphere for modern societies where public administration, technocracy, economism and scientism threaten to occult politics, and where political liberalism confuses the political framework with politics itself. But her use of sharp distinctionswhere the sphere of necessity (labour) excludes freedom (action), and where the social question is excluded from politics properhave deep consequences for her political thought. It means, among other things, that her conceptualization of authentic politics does not include institutionalization, such as the positing of laws. She is not opposed to such institutionalization, of course, but she treats it as part of a different context, in discussions of what she calls moments of constitution and foundation, whose logic is covenanting and the making and keeping of promises (see, especially, Arendt, 1990). A significant portion of the literature on Arendt is devoted to saving her political thought from its weaknesses and blind spots. In The Greek Polis and the Creation of Democracy (1991), Castoriadis addresses some of the problems that emerge from Arendts analyses, for example that it is very hard to defend democracy on the basis of her conception of the Greek polis.9 In a less generous remark, he points out that her criteria are not enough to distinguish politics from other activities, as surely Hitler and Stalin and their infamous companions have revealed who they were through deeds and speech (Castoriadis, 1991: 122), yet they destroyed politics. And even if it can be objected that Hitler and Stalin do not fill Arendts prerequisites of appearing before equals in a public space, the point still remains that Arendts notion of politics at this point is both too narrow and too unspecific. Politics must also be about something (other than itself) and the content of utterances, issues and causes should also qualify as political or apolitical (Castoriadis, 1991; Torgerson, 1999; Villa, 1996). Moreover, Arendts scheme cannot account for the fact that political changes have historically been

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

374

European Journal of Social Theory 15(3)

instigated by agents whose motive was precisely thefor Arendt, unpolitical social question. Castoriadis rightly points out that even though social questions about economic distribution and material conditions may not be political in themselves, they could (and should) still be treated and decided upon in political processes. Questions about different ways to organize oneself as society, judging and choosing between different institutions of society is, after all, the political question par excellence (Castoriadis, 1991: 101). Nor is it granted that to treat social questions politically necessarily leads to the instrumentalization of politics, as Arendt claims (1990: 57, 59ff, 112). In his comments to Arendt, Castoriadis clearly thinks that politics can have goals, although in other texts he also stresses the open-ended character of political activities (Castoriadis, 1987: 71114, 1997c: 12536).10 The struggle for influence by the working class, for example, is an obvious case of genuine politics for Castoriadis, but not for Arendt, who would exclude from politics all kinds of struggles on behalf of particular interests, poverty included.11 Castoriadis also disagrees with Arendts thesis that legislative activity was a secondary aspect of politics in ancient Greece, pointing out that Aristotle counts 13 revolutions in Athens; that is, changes in the fundamental (constitutional) legislation (Castoriadis, 1991: 102). When Arendt (1989) claims that the Greek political framework and legislature were something that was constructed before the political activity itself took place, i.e. fabricated, or erected, like housing, this is simply misleading for communities whose constitution-building was part of their own politics and no less political than any of the actions it was supposed to house and regulate (Waldron, 2000: 204). Finally, when Arendt denies that politics can have goals beyond itself, defining all social and economic questions as belonging to the outside of genuine politics, her account of historical events simply becomes unacceptable to professional historians (Hobsbawm, 2006; Waldron, 2000). But let us not forget that there are other strands in Arendts work than the rigid distinctions worked out in The Human Condition which have been the focus so far. I am thinking of the insistence throughout her work on the importance of institutions. In On Revolution and Between Past and Future she highlights this dimension through her discussions about the meaning of tradition, authority and the making of promises which serves to constitute a common world. The existence of an institutional framework is of the utmost importance for Arendt: it is what makes action, politics and even revolutions, possible (Arendt 1989, 1990, 2006b). We can therefore say that there are two essential aspects in Arendts political thought: the expressivist, performative dimension presented above and the (less discussed) political framework, such as constitutions and councils. In the following passage, the relation between them is made explicit:
The grammar of action: that action is the only human faculty that demands a plurality of men; and the syntax of power: that power is the only human attribute which applies solely to the worldly in-between space by which men are mutually related, combine in the act of foundation by virtue of the making and the keeping of promises, which, in the realm of politics, may well be the highest human faculty (Arendt, 1990: 175, my emphasis).

A common world is that which lies between people, separating them and at the same time holding them together:

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

Straume

375

To live together in the world means essentially that a world of things is between those who have it in common, as a table is located between those who sit around it; the world, like every in-between, relates and separates men at the same time. The public realm, as the common world, gathers us together and yet prevents our falling over each other, so to speak (Arendt, 1989: 52).

The common world consists of words and deeds, but, of course, also institutions in a wide sense of the term. In fact, instituted society (to use the Castoriadian term) is of the utmost importance to Arendt: it needs protection for the sake of protecting our humanity. And even though she does not see institutions as the product of politics proper, it is hard to see why the creation of institutions, especially constitutions, should not be a political matter.

Dichotomy and plurality


I now want to discuss how the respective works of Arendt and Castoriadis can help us form an inspiring and constructive understanding of political creation. The previous section related Arendts critique of Marx and the modern tradition. A question yet to be addressed is whether this critique can also be aimed at Castoriadiss project of autonomy, because, as we have seen, politics for him is largely about creating institutions while Arendt is deeply sceptical about this notion, which for her occludes genuine politics. The question, which merits some consideration, requires an introduction to Castoriadiss social ontology. On the one hand, like Arendt, Castoriadis is critical of theorizing not only politics, but also society and history. On the other hand he clearly thinks that political activities can (and should) have goals, and he also thinks that autonomous societies are preferable to heteronomous ones; thus, he has a certain vision for politics. In the first part of The Imaginary Institution of Society, called Marxism and Revolutionary Theory, Castoriadis criticizes both the idea of founding praxis upon a theory, and the idea that as a theory of the social is impossible, praxis must be blind (Castoriadis, 1987: 71ff).12 He writes:
To be sure, praxis is a conscious activity and can only exist as lucid activity, but it is something quite different from the application of prior knowledge [ . . . ]. It is based on knowledge, but this knowledge is always fragmentary and provisional. It is fragmentary because there can be no exhaustive theory of humanity and of history; it is provisional because praxis itself constantly gives rise to new knowledge [ . . . ] The theory can never be given beforehand, because it constantly emerges out of the activity itself. The clarification and transformation of reality progress together in praxis, each conditioning the other (Castoriadis, 1987: 76).

This critique resembles and expands Arendts critique of Marx. Castoriadiss notion of politics combines rationality with anti-foundationalism and lucidity with radical creation (creation ex nihilo). On his account, there can be no political expert-knowledge, since:
If a full and certain knowledge (episteme) of the human domain were possible, politics would immediately come to an end, and democracy would be both impossible and absurd:

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

376

European Journal of Social Theory 15(3)

democracy implies that all citizens have the possibility of attaining a correct doxa and that nobody possesses an episteme of things political (Castoriadis, 1991: 104).

Instead of theory and certain knowledge Castoriadis sees the history of human societies as a matter of creation: self-creation deployed as history (1997c: 13). History is the creation of social forms: complex, irreducible forms that do not accord to laws or principles. But as traditional thought is by and large oblivious towards notions such as the imagination and creation, philosophy has been unable to conceptualize the true nature of the social-historical, according to Castoriadis:
Here, inherited ontology and logic are helpless: they are bound to ignore the proper being of the social-historical. Not only is creation for this ontology and logic a dirty word (except in a theological context [ . . . ]) but also this ontology is inevitably driven to ask, Creation by whom? Yet creation, as the work of the social imaginary, of the instituting society [ . . . ], is the mode of being of the social-historical field, by means of which this field is. Society is self-creation deployed as history. To recognize this and to stop asking meaningless questions about subjects and substances or causes requires, to be sure, a radical ontological conversion (Castoriadis, 1997c: 1314).

To theorize the social-historical, as Marx did, is therefore a way to cover up these disturbing notions.13 History, for Castoriadis, is not something that happens to a given society, nor is a society a kind of embodiment of something outside of itself. This is a problem for traditional philosophy, since:
. . . the inherited way of thinking has never been able to separate out the true object of [the question of the social-historical] and to consider it for itself. This object has almost always been split into a society, related to something other than itself and, generally, to a norm, end, or telos grounded in something else, and a history, considered as something that happens to this society, as a disturbance in relation to a given norm or as an organic or dialectical development towards this norm, end or telos (Castoriadis, 1987: 167).

But Castoriadis is not an advocate of the unpredictable as pure contingency. In a text e (The published in the midst of the uprisings of May, 1968, La revolution anticipe anticipated revolution), Castoriadis names the challenges for what he sees as a possibly revolutionary movement.14 In his view, a movement should posit itself and declare its intentions, as to abstain from doing so means to abstain from political power. He especially warns the students against existing dichotomies posed as mutually exclusive options, for instance, when there is either the imagination or the organization; creativity or reality. This warning is worthy of some consideration as it also applies to Arendts conception of authentic politics which halts before the act of making. The ideological dichotomy is set between reality and the imaginary: The revolutionary students feel an antinomy between action and reflection: between spontaneity and organization, between truth of act and coherence of speech, between imagination and project. Their perception of this antinomy is what consciously or unconsciously lies behind their hesitations (Castoriadis, 1993: 130). In ordinary discourse, politics is often perceived as something dull, hardened or set; it signifies bureaucracy and non-creativity

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

Straume

377

[well illustrated by Jacques Rancie ` res (1995) concept of la police]. But it also signifies hard reality, that which in the end must have a final say, the non-eligible. Political institutions and their keepers seem real in a commanding way: You can play all you like, but in the end we all have to grow up and face reality, i.e., to comply. If, correspondingly, the political repertoire of actions and ideas is limited to the other side of the dichotomy, such as happenings, the imagination, the event, the carnivalesque or showing who one is (Arendt), we are actually feeding into the existing political system. To accept the dichotomy and, hence, to restrict our political activities to just one side out of fear of being captive to the other means, for Castoriadis, to submit to the (hierarchical) structures of the society in question. It also means saying that only one part of the dichotomy can be real, whereas the other becomes purely imaginary in the sense of fictional, non-real. One thing must be made clear at this point. As Castoriadis also recognizes, there are cupere e) by good reasons to fear that a new (proto-political) initiative can be co-opted (re already existing organizations. The students of May 1968 had good reasons to be sceptical of the leaders of the existing left-wing organizations, having experienced how revolutionary talk had been turned into sterile dogma; left-wing organizations turned bureaucratic and routine-driven; projects replaced by rigid programme and political discourse having been mystified (Castoriadis, 1993). Interestingly enough though, Castoriadis remarks that those who fear such recuperation are still on the old ground; they are talking from within the existing power structures, whereas the ground for a revolutionary movement must be defined anew, that is, created and defined by the new movement:
To accept this antinomy as valid, final, and insurmountable is to accept the very essence of bureaucratic-capitalist ideology. It is to accept the existing philosophy and reality. It is to reject a real attempt at transforming the world. It is to integrate the revolution into the established historical order (Castoriadis, 1993: 130).

The point to remember is that it will always be in the interest of the powers that be to facilitate change in order to swallow it, or use it to renew and refine the existing power structures. Hence, if one accepts the dichotomies offered by the social order and choose one side against the other, one is already playing the game of the instituted power. It is therefore imperative, says Castoriadis (1993), that the would-be revolutionary movement gives itself form. It must organize itself, give itself a face and articulate something to which it is willing to commit itself (a programme), albeit temporarily. By giving itself a new form, the revolutionary movement leaves the old ground with its definitions, dichotomies and dilemmas. This will also make the movement immune to co-optation, at least for some time. Furthermore, such self-positing is the only way to transgress hierarchies and divisions in society that tend to reproduce themselves in ever new versions. This advice to the would-be revolutionaries demonstrates that genuine politics for Castoriadis here means poiesis, that is to create institutions in a conscious, explicit and lucid manner. We are now in a position to consider the question whether Castoriadiss project resembles that of Marx (or Marxism) in such a way that Arendts critique of work (poiesis) replacing action (praxis)15 can also be turned against Castoriadis. Clearly, the answer is no. Firstly, even if the project of autonomy involves elucidation,

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

378

European Journal of Social Theory 15(3)

this does not imply that political creation equals transparent or exhaustively planned actions. Secondly, as we have seen, Arendt herself recognizes the importance of institutionalization, which means that her notion of politics in The Human Condition is insufficient. Compared with Arendts political expressivism, Castoriadiss notion of elucidation comes forth as the more politicized alternative. By naming and de-masking power relations and taking social matters seriously in a theoretical context, his political thought seems more orientated toward praxis. Other aspects of Arendts thought, however, pose more of a challenge to Castoriadis, particularly when it comes to conceptualizing political, collective subjectivity in terms of plurality. Where the basic unit of Arendts socio-political analyses is ultimately the individual,16 Castoriadis insists that all analyses of political and social phenomena must depart from the social-historical level and certainly not from inter-subjectivity, of which Arendts plurality is an instance. For Castoriadis, [t]he social-historical is neither the unending addition of intersubjective networks (although it is this too), nor, of course, is it their simple product (1987: 108). Castoriadis emphasizes the limited capacity of inter-subjective relations in establishing the social level, since for him socially instituted meaning is always primary to the constitution of individuals and, in fact, circumscribes what can be seen as meaningful activities, including inter-subjectivity. Castoriadis makes a conceptual distinction between the individual, which is always socialized, and the psyche, which is the irreducible counterpart of the social-historical. In his later years (after the Socialisme ou Barbarie period), he displayed little interest in discussing philosophy at the inter-subjective, already socialized-qua-instituted level. This could be a coincidence rather than a systematic flaw, but the fact remains that he did not work out an adequate conceptual apparatus for dealing with the political condition of plurality. In his philosophical writings, subjectivity is usually related to micro- and macro-levels, not the in-between levels. In this respect, Arendts thought can elucidate a lacuna in Castoriadiss thought by bringing attention to the who of political creationor better, the whos that create a world between them through words and deeds (Arendt, 1989; 1990). Plurality asserts that while the subjects occupy different places in the world, they are connected. In comparison, the concepts Castoriadis uses to denote collective agency in his later worksthe anonymous collective, the social-historical, the instituting social imaginary and the instituting society are, in my opinion, too abstract for many practical purposes such as analyses of social phenomena. Thus, Arendts concept of plurality represents an important dimension of the politically active, collective subject (like the demos of antiquity); a dimension that is lacking in (the later) Castoriadis. Even though Arendt does not think of politics as making (something), her work has several openings towards creation as spontaneity and newness. The notion of creation can be found in the spontaneous acting in concert that characterizes revolutions (Arendt, 1990). The capacity to create something radically new is also inherent in the faculty of natality, where every person is a new beginning (Arendt, 2006b). On another level, she notes how thoughts are forced out of their tendency towards closure when people go visiting other people whose position in the world is different from their own (another aspect of plurality). This opening belongs to the faculty of the imagination. As people occupy different places in the instituted world, they also hold different

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

Straume

379

viewpoints and different views from each other. The idea that one could go visiting by using the imagination was rather brusquely dismissed by Castoriadis (1991), who claimed that in order to put oneself in anothers position one would simply have to become somebody else. But Arendt makes a good case for using the imagination on the level of political inter-subjectivity, not only for remaining open to and interested in other viewpoints, but in order to position ourselves politically and pass judgments. Plurality can thus be seen as a precondition for creativity and creation, as a plurality of viewpoints between people, dissent and disagreements constitute productive tensions. It does not so much pertain to what people aretheir identitiesas to what they do; their contributions in the political sphere (Ringvej, 2011). Even though Castoriadis could probably agree with many of these points, he has not elaborated on them. His emphasis is on ontology and his preoccupation is irreducibility and anti-reductionism as exemplified in the relationship between the social-historical and the psyche presented above. These concerns also affect his concept of autonomy, which, in his later works, consists of philosophical inquiry and problematization, elucidation and autogestion, but without the inter-subjective emphasis that can be found in Arendts notion of a common world. Thus, Castoriadiss later works become curiously void of subjects. However, I see no reason why further work on Castoriadiss conceptual apparatus, for example to make it more applicable to empirical analyses of social phenomena, could not include a concept like plurality. A methodology of elucidation would logically imply worldliness as plurality and action. In such a reconstruction, the work of Arendt could be helpful, their similarities taken into account, and vice versa, as I have already argued.

The import of politics proper


Both Arendt and Castoriadis are attracting increasing scholarly interest. This is partly a result of their inspiring modes of doing philosophy, but there can be little doubt that their works are also seen as relevant in understanding contemporary issues as an alternative beyond analyticliberal and post-modern approaches. The typically modern tendencies of de-politicization that were identified by Arendt in The Human Condition are, for example by no means exhausted. There are also relevant applications for her critique of the social, albeit in a tempered form, such as her warning against a situation where interest groups (alone) define the political field. There are many examples that such groups have tried to destroy the political openness of modern forms of democracy, notably lobby groups and corporations. To modify her scheme, however, we could look to another influential political thinker, Alain Touraine (2000), and argue that the relevant demarcation is not between social and political questions as such, but rather between what Touraine calls social and societal movements. While social movements struggle for their (particular) interests, societal groups become (part of) political movements whose concern is society as a whole, not just their own interests. In such a framework, the instrumental character of the former can be contrasted to the politicized approach of the latter without sacrificing socio-economic questions altogether. To round off, a brief discussion of the actuality of the two thinkers political ideas seems fitting. For example, in what way can their ideas about politics proper, democracy and revolutions elucidate the uprisings in the Arab countries, Southern Europe and

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

380

European Journal of Social Theory 15(3)

beyond that followed the financial crisis from 2008? Just a few general remarks are possible here. Firstly, it seems clear that political action of the revolutionary kind is not something planned in advance. At the start of a revolution, everything happens very fast. For instance, hardly anyone could have foreseen the speed and efficiency with which the people of Tunisia and Egypt forced their leaders to resign from power in the spring of 2011. When large groups of people suddenly cease to fear for their own lives, as did the Tunisian vegetable seller Mohamed Bouazizi who set himself on fire in a desperate protest against the authoritiesthe beginning, if not the cause, of the Tunisian revolutiontyranny loses much of its grip. With the withdrawal of popular consent, the institutions of explicit power immediately fail, leaving two paths possible for the tyrants: escalating violence or resignation. In this respect, there are parallels between the demise of the North African regimes and the very rapid crumbling of the Eastern European block (notably the Berlin Wall and Ceaus escus Romania). In On Revolution, Arendt asserts that people acting in concert represent a greater power than the force of violence and weapons (Arendt, 1990). This was indeed demonstrated by the relatively peaceful overthrow of the regime in Tunisia. Her accompanying claim that brute force does not bring about any real societal change, has similarly been proven true by several (or all) Western invasions, for example in Iraq, Afghanistan and Libya. However, even though there are similarities in various historical cases, there can be no theory of revolutions as such. Revolutions and revolts are often expressions of the unexpected will of a people: spontaneously enacted, and therefore effective. At the time of writing, there are major demonstrations in regions that have a long tradition of popular manifestations, such as Greece and Spain, and, most recently, in the USA with occupation of the financial centre, Wall Street. New initiatives are born every day, inspired by the so-called Arab Spring of 2011, and there are worldwide campaigns of solidarity and protest (for example Indignad@s, Real Democracy NOW!; We Are The 99%). These initiatives have no appointed leaders and a rather thin agenda. Their indignation is aimed at political structures that favour finance capital over peoples work and welfare.17 The question is, once again, whether these spontaneous protests can turn into organized form without losing their political momentum. There are also reasons to fear a political backlash, as economic and military forces are more than ready to fill the power vacuums as they emerge. What seems certain is that it is counterproductive to criticize and doubt these movements in their early stages, as they are in the process of creation and mainly driven by young (often well educated) people. As Castoriadis (1987) has argued, history is full of forms that are other (not merely different) to those already in existence. As long as there is politics, in the strong and explicit sense, new forms will emerge, even though they can be hard to recognize at first. The open-endedness of the on-going revolts and the inadequacy of theory to guide analyses seem to point in favour of the perspectives of Arendt and Castoriadis. At the time of writing, nobody knows whether these processes of autonomy and action will result in something entirely new.18 If the people in revolt should manage to name themselves and create new institutionsbeyond the significations of corporate capitalismgreat efforts are required. Therefore, let us hope that the founding moment will be kept open for an extended period of time to allow for reflective discussion about what constitutes fair and just institutions. In other words, our hope

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

Straume

381

is for a new constitution, in a wide sense of the term, which will not look too much like the recipes of capitalist democracy that we already know too well. Notes
1. Their common interests and philosophical parallels have been noted by several scholars (see Poizat, 2007; Ramsay, 2003; Whitebook, 1998; Zerilli, 2002). 2. Castoriadis discusses their shared interests in a talk at an Arendt memorial symposium in 1982 (The Greek Polis and the Creation of Democracy in Castoriadis, 1991: 81123 and in abbreviated form in Castoriadis 1997a: 26789). 3. The political is for Arendt synonymous to Castoriadiss politics. To prevent misunderstandings, I use the term the political field to designate what Castoriadis calls the political. A further benefit is to stay clear of Carl Schmitts notion of the political, which has a third meaning. 4. An appropriate question, which cannot be pursued here, is the influence of the early Heidegger that looms in the background of both thinkers. See Dana Villa (1996) on how Heidegger served as a (negative and positive) prerequisite for Arendts philosophy of political action. 5. In The Imaginary Institution of Society, Castoriadis set forth to create a philosophy of doing, but he never really carried through his intention (Arnason, 1991). 6. The distinctions are operative in Arendt (1989, 1990) and in the essay What is Freedom? (Arendt, 2006a). 7. The critique of the social, which Arendt set forth in On Revolution, was largely associated with the Jacobin terror following the French Revolution, but also the increasing bureaucratization and technocratic regimes of the 1950s, where an important part was played by the social sciences. In the French Revolution, a wave of mass slaughtering, censorship and distrust was unleashed in the name of liberty, equality and faternity. Politics was destroyed for an allegedly higher purpose, thus freedom itself was sacrificed for the idea of freedom, that is, a theory (Arendt, 1990). 8. From her analyses in The Origins of Totalitarianism, Arendt was deeply concerned with the loss of a common world and individuality that characterized Nazism and Stalinism. This fear made a significant mark on her political thought (Canovan, 1994; Villa, 1996). 9. Arendt is a rather ambiguous democrat, at best. Her sources of inspiration such as Burckhardt, Nietzsche, Machiavelli, Heidegger and Homeric ideals attest to this. Another important source is the existentialist Karl Jaspers. 10. Castoriadis points out that the Greek term techne had a double meaning that Aristotle knew, but did not clarify, as both mimesis, imitation, and poiesis, creation. Techne and praxis would then meet in poiesis , and through this connection Plato and Aristotle could co-think work (as techne ) and action (as praxis). But already with Plato, techne was reduced to imitation (mimesis ), thus dividing work from politics (Castoriadis, 1984: 22959). This occultation could be an important premise for Arendts reading of Aristotle in The Human Condition. 11. This does not mean that Arendt does not care for problems such as poverty; her point is that they should be dealt with in a different context, which would probably mean technocratically. 12. This paper was first published in Socialisme ou Barbarie, 196465. 13. Where Arendt sees a covering of the agent, Castoriadis sees a covering of creation. The two points are in essence the same: the covering of political creation.

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

382

European Journal of Social Theory 15(3)

`che, May 68 (1968, Paris: Fayard): a collection of 14. Castoriadis (1993). First edition in La Bre essays together with Claude Lefort and Edgar Morin. 15. More precisely, in Marxism Arendt (1989) saw first a conflation of work and labour, and then a further occultation of action. 16. Arendt (1989) does not use the term individual in this connection, which for her denotes the mass individual of the social sciences. 17. These movements have spread from Spain, starting in May 2011, when a square in Madrid was occupied for a whole month. Camps were then established in large and smaller cities and the movement spread to suburban areas and towns where coordinated assemblies were established. 18. Castoriadis saw very little potential for autonomy in monotheistic and traditional societies of Eastern or Muslim origin. Autonomy is for him a Graeco-Western invention.

References
Arendt H (1989) [1958] The Human Condition. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Arendt H (1990) [1963] On Revolution. London: Penguin. Arendt H (2004) [1948/1951] The Origins of Totalitarianism. New York: Shocken. Arendt H (2006a) [1960] What is Freedom?. In: Between Past and Future. Eight Exercises in Political Thought. New York: Penguin. Arendt H (2006b) Between Past and Future. Eight Exercises in Political Thought. New York: Penguin. Arnason J P (1991) Praxis and actionmainstream theories and Marxian correctives. Thesis Eleven 29: 6381. Castoriadis C (1984) Crossroads in the Labyrinth (Soper K and Ryle M H, transl.). Brighton: Harvester Press. Castoriadis C (1987) The Imaginary Institution of Society (Blamey K, transl.) Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Castoriadis C (1988) Political and Social Writings, Volume 2, 19551960: From the Workers Struggle Against Bureaucracy to Revolution in the Age of Modern Capitalism (Curtis D A, ed., transl.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Castoriadis C (1991) Philosophy, Politics, Autonomy. Essays in Political Philosophy (Curtis D A, transl.). New York: Oxford University Press. Castoriadis C (1993) The Anticipated Revolution. In: Castoriadis C Political and Social Writings, Volume 3 (1961-1971) Curtis D A, ed., transl.). London: University of Minnesota Press. Castoriadis C (1997a) The Castoriadis Reader (Curtis D A, ed., transl.). Oxford: Blackwell. Castoriadis C (1997b) Democracy as procedure and democracy as regime. Constellations 4: 118. Castoriadis C (1997c) World in Fragments. Writings on Politics, Society, Psychoanalysis and the Imagination (Curtis D A, transl.). Stanford: Stanford University Press. Castoriadis C (2007) Figures of the Thinkable (Arnold H, transl.). Stanford: Stanford University Press. Canovan M (1994) Hannah Arendt. A Reinterpretation of her Political Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Forti S (2006) The guilt of the tradition. In: Williams G (ed.) Hannah Arendt: Critical Assessments of Leading Political Philosophers, Vol. IV. London: Routledge.

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

Straume

383

Hobsbawm E J (2006) Hannah Arendt on revolution. In: Williams G (ed.) Hannah Arendt: Critical Assessments of Leading Political Philosophers, Vol. II. London: Routledge. Kateb G (2000) Political action: its nature and advantages. In: Villa D (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pitkin H F (1998) The Attack of the Blob. Hannah Arendts Concept of the Social. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Poizat J-C (2007) Limagination chez Cornelius Castoriadis et Hannah Arendt: Le politique entre pouvoir de cre ation et pouvoir de re ve lation. In: Bachofen B, Elbaz S and Poirier N (eds) ditions du Sandre. inventer lautonomie. Paris: E Cornelius Castoriadis: Re sententePolitique et Philosophie. Paris: Galile Rancie ` re J (1995) La Me e. Ramsay A (2003) Den forskande aktivisten [The Researching Militant]. Res Publica no. 58: 2842 Ringvej M (2011) Makten og ordene. Demokrati og ytringsfrihet fra Athen til Eidsvoll [The Power and the Words. Democracy and Freedom of Speech from Athens to Eidsvoll]. Oslo: Humanist. Torgerson D R (1999) The Promise of Green Politics. Environmentalism and the Public Sphere. Durham/London: Duke. Touraine A (2000) Can We Live Together? Equality and Difference. Cambridge: Polity Press. Villa D R (1996) Arendt and Heidegger. New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Villa D R (ed.) (2000) The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Villa D R (2000) Introduction: the development of Arendts political thought. In Villa D (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Waldron J (2000) Arendts constitutional politics. In: Villa D (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Williams G (ed.) (2006) Hannah Arendt: Critical Assessments of Leading Political Philosophers. Vol. IIV. London: Routledge. Whitebook J (1985) Cornelius Castoriadis: Crossroads in the labyrinth. Telos 63: 22839. Whitebook J (1998: Requiem for a Selbstdenker: Cornelius Castoriadis (19221997). Constellations 5: 14160. Zerilli L (2002) Castoriadis, Arendt, and the problem of the new. Constellations 9: 54053.

About the author


Ingerid S. Straume is a philosopher of education based at the University of Oslo. The subject of her PhD thesis from 2010 is Castoriadiss thoughts on democracy and paideia. She has published articles on environmental politics, moral philosophy, political philosophy and education, and edited the anthology Depoliticization: The Political Imaginary of Global Capitalism (with J.F. Humphrey, Aarhus University Press, 2011). Address: University of Oslo, University of Oslo Library, PO Box 1009 Blindern, 0315 Oslo, Norway [email: ingerid.straume@ub.uio.no]

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Javier Benyo on October 22, 2012

También podría gustarte