Está en la página 1de 18

Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 2004, volume 22, pages 157 ^ 173

DOI:10.1068/d315t

Secondhandedness: consumption, disposal, and absent presence


Kevin Hetherington
Department of Sociology, Lancaster University, Lancaster LA1 4YL, England; e-mail: k.hetherington@lancaster.ac.uk Received 10 March 2002; in revised form 11 February 2003

Abstract. In this paper I argue that in the now-extensive work on the sociology of consumption there is very little that addresses directly the important issue of disposal. Furthermore, I argue that disposal is not just about questions of waste and rubbish but is implicated more broadly in the ways in which people manage absence within social relations. I develop this argument through a critical engagement with the work of Mary Douglas, Rolland Munro, Michael Thompson, and Robert Hertz. I seek to show that disposal is never final as is implied by the notion of rubbish but involves issues of managing social relations and their representation around themes of movement, transformation, incompleteness, and return. I suggest that rather than see the rubbish bin as the archetypal conduit of disposal within consumer practices the door might be seen as a better example. This has implications for understanding questions of representation, ethics, and the management of social relations within the practices of consuming.

Introduction The growing academic interest in consumption in recent years has, in large part, been a product of the cultural turn within social science. That is not to say that consumption as an issue was not there in the past. Thorstein Veblen's work on the new rich, or leisure class, in the United States at the end of the 19th century (1991 [1899]), Frankfurt School critiques of the culture industry (Adorno and Horkheimer, 1979 [1944]) and of the false needs created by capitalism (Marcuse, 1968), as well as writing on spectacle and the colonisation of everyday life by commodification (Baudrillard, 1996 [1968]; 1998 [1970]; Debord, 1977 [1967]; Lefebvre, 1971), have all made a significant contribution to our understanding of consumption and consumer culture (for an overview and discussion see Miller, 1987; Slater, 1997). What has changed is that the more recent analysis of consumption has sought to valorise it as a creative source of cultural or in some cases individual expression, lifestyle, and taste rather than see it as a fetishistic expression of alienation and false needs (such as in Haug, 1986 [1971]; Marx, 1938 [1867]). As in audience research, the general move in much of this work on consumption has been towards recognising the skilled and creative person making a social life for themselves through consumer practices (Douglas and Isherwood, 1980; Featherstone, 1991; Gabriel and Lang, 1995; Lury, 1996; Miller, 1995; Shields, 1992). Even so, there have been serious differences of opinion within this field. In particular, some of this work has come in for criticism for overemphasising the more spectacular within consumption cultures. The associated focus on consumption as indicative of a postmodern culture, with much emphasis on style and fashion (high and street), has been criticised for overlooking more routine forms of consumption (or provisioning) (see Clark, 1999; Dant, 2000; Gregson, 1993; 1997; Miller, 1998; Warde, 1997). The alternative has been to suggest we concentrate on ordinary consumption, and on routine provisioning. Spatially it is either the shopping mall (Shields, 1989) or the boot sale or charity shop (Gregson et al, 2002) that exemplifies the locus of these two different positions.

158

K Hetherington

One way in which to understand these two recent approaches to consumption, therefore, is to look at the point in the consumption process that they focus on. Culturalist approaches tend to concentrate on the beginnings in the process of consuminginfluences of image, style, brand, advertising, and buying practices or on the significance of the `dream-world' spaces of consumption (for an illustration of this approach see Bowlby, 1985; Lury, 1996; Shields, 1992; Williams, 1982).(1) Such approaches highlight the importance of acquiring and having things and of creating lifestyles and identities through consumption. They look at the `front end' of consumption. Those more critical of such an emphasis on the spectacular focus instead not only on routine consumption but also on issues of utilityon what people do with their shopping, the services they obtain, the DIY or self-provisioning they engage in after they have seen the adverts and acquired the goods (Miller, 1998; Pahl, 1984; Warde, 1997). In the first case the consumer is constituted as a bricoleur of style, in the second more as a bricoleur of everyday practice, kinship, class, or gender relations. From both positions we now know a good deal about consumer habits, tastes, lifestyles as well as about how households consume and also about class and gender patterns of consuming. What we know little about, however, is the role that disposal plays within the consumer's activity. A detailed library-based, and Internet-based search on the word `disposal' in social-science indexes and abstracts will reveal that it tends to come attached to the words `environmental' and `bomb'. A search in my own university library recently revealed over seventy publications on disposal, the majority of which were local-authority oversize pamphlets on slurry and sewage. Indeed, it would seem that in this literature disposal is synonymous with forms of waste (Hawkins, 2000). Linked to this is work on environmentalism and so-called ethical or green consumption. Ethical-consumption arguments from groups like Friends of the Earth or Greenpeace often make the claim that we live in an unethical, throwaway society, submerging the world and future generations in toxic pollution and waste and that such consumption is indicative of a utilitarian or selfish form of pleasure seeking with no real concern for the consequences. My aim in this paper is not simply to suggest that the disposal part of the consumption process (as its end point) is something that has been neglected in recent work on consuming and to then redress that omission (for such an argument see O'Brien, 1999) but instead to suggest that disposal be seen as a necessary issue integral to the whole process of viewing consuming as a social activity. In other words, I suggest that studying consumption makes no sense unless we consider the role of disposing as an integral part of the totality of what consumer activity is all about. Recognising this may allow us to address some of these ethical questions too. Whereas the trope of waste is often taken as indicative of the uncaring individualism of consumption, a focus on disposal as a recursive process suggests it to be, instead, thoroughly constitutive of social and indeed ethical activity. There is, of course, an anthropological literature on `waste' that treats it as more than a category suitable for the oversize local-authority report: studies of the gift and potlatch (Mauss, 1991 [1950]; Titmuss, 1970), burial rites (Hertz, 1960 [1907]), pollution (Douglas, 1984 [1966]), and sacrifice are all noteworthy attempts to locate how getting rid of things is integral to the performance of social relations, kinship networks, and ritual knowledge and activity (Girard, 1977; Hubert and Mauss, 1964 [1899]). Indeed, there have been serious attempts to understand consumption by using some of these categories (Bataille, 1991 [1967]; Douglas and Isherwood, 1980;
(1) This is also related to the development of more historical work on shopping, particularly concentrating on its cultural significance for women (see Bowlby, 2000; Nava, 1992).

Secondhandedness: consumption, disposal and absent presence

159

Miller, 1998; Sahlins, 1972). All the same, it is `getting rid of things or meanings' rather than the recursivity of disposal in a fuller sense, I contend, that much of this work tends to emphasise. Indeed, what is often missing is a sense that disposal is a continual practice of engaging with making and holding things in a state of absence, any notion of return (beyond simple equations of return with green recycling), or any notion of understanding how something can be in a state of abeyance or `at your disposal' and what the effects of that might be. Work on disposal in this broader anthropological sense is in very limited supply indeed (see Derrida, 1994; Munro, 1995; 1998; Strathern, 1999; Thompson, 1979). My criticism of work that either ignores disposal or treats it solely as a category of waste or wasting is that it does not grasp its dynamic and performative role within consumption. Waste suggests too final a singular act of closure, one that does not actually occur in practice. Though there are good histories of how the social and technical processes of dealing with rubbish have changed over time (for example, Strasser, 2000), they do not pay any attention to other senses of disposal, nor to how that which has been turned into rubbish tends to have the ability to return. Disposal, I contend, is not primarily about waste but about placing. It is as much a spatial as a temporal category. Terms like `waste disposal' and `waste management' are misnomers. Rather, disposal is about placing absences and this has consequences for how we think about `social relations'. If we are to understand what disposal means in relation to consumption we would do well to analyse it as such and to consider how consumers manage and are managed by the absent rather than just how they throw things away. Getting rid of something is never simply an act of waste disposal. Issues of agency and representation (and nonrepresentation) get drawn in too. When we dispose of something to handa material form of some kindwe do not necessarily get rid of its semiotic presence and the effects that are generated around that. Disposal, then, is concerned with not just semiotic mobility but also mutability and translation as well (on translation see Brown, 1981; Callon, 1986). My argument is that when discussing disposal we should begin with a counterintuitive move that questions from the start the idea of disposal as a final state of rubbishing. My purpose is to suggest that in so doing we might understand more about the processes of consuming than if we just assume disposal to be the last act that leads inexorably to a closure of a particular sequence of production ^ consumption events. Such an approach aims to challenge the commonsense idea that production ^ consumption ^ disposal follows in an inevitable, discrete, linear temporal sequence. Such a view may suit the methodological individualism of much economic writing on consumption, or the fondness for linear narrative within social science, but it is not particularly helpful. As a secondary and more abstract theme, this argument also challenges the idea that we should think only sociologically about issues of presence. The absent can have just as much of an effect upon relations as recognisable forms of presence can have. Social relations are performed not only around what is there but sometimes also around the presence of what is not. Absence, I argue, is not just a philosophical concept, it is also a distinctly sociological one. Indeed the category of absence can have a significant presence in social relations and in material culture. Given the social rather than individual basis of consumption acts (see Douglas and Isherwood, 1980), this has implications not only for what we do to things but also for how those things (and their absence) are implicated in how we do social relations (Callon, 1986; Latour, 1993). Disposal, then, is fundamentally implicated in the making of modes of representational order it helps to make a society make senseeven though that is often done in a fluid manner and at a highly local, mundane and material level.

160

K Hetherington

In order to address these issues we need to consider the spatiality of disposal more fully, particularly around these issues of presence and absence. Here, after a discussion of work on disposal by Mary Douglas (1984), Rolland Munro (1995; 1998), and Michael Thompson (1979), I adapt Robert Hertz's work on what might be called the anthropology of the gap implied in his discussion of human burial practices (1960) and apply it to understanding the dynamics of disposing of things (what I will call here secondhandedness) as a means of addressing the issue of how ordering work gets done around some of the central forms of disposal: abeyance, return, storage, removal, and haunting. The absence of disposal The recent writing that does exist on disposal is small but useful, though it is as yet undeveloped and still often takes the limited `problem' of waste as its central theme (Chappells and Shove, 1999; Hawkins, 2000; Munro, 1995; 1998; O'Brien, 1999; Strathern, 1999). In addressing the relationship between consumption the associated acts of acquiring, possessing, valuing, exchanging, and using an object, good, or service of some kind and disposal, we can find some guidance from earlier work on the relationship between consumption and production. First discussed by Karl Marx in the Grundrisse (1973 [1939]) and repeated many times since, we find the argument that there is never an altogether clear-cut distinction between production and consumption, nor a simple temporal sequence to these processes (see Lury, 1996; Pahl, 1984; Warde, 1997). We may buy something from a shop that has been produced and we can, in acquiring and using it or in attributing some significance to that object, be said to be consuming it. However, in so doing, productive work may still be required of us. A flat-pack table still needs work done to it in order for it to be assembled for use; a ready-cooked meal still needs to be heated up before it is eaten and then there is the washing up to be done afterwards. Production and consumption are entangled together in these and other cases. They also entangle time into the process in a nonlinear way as well as matters of technique (see Latour, 2002). Production does not always come before consumption; it may also come after in the sequence of events. Likewise, to produce something itself requires prior acts of consumption before it can be made ready for consumption. A carpenter has to acquire wood, an artist paint, and so on. We should consider disposal in the same light as these other entanglements. It is not just the last act in a sequence that runs from production to consumption to disposal, but is recursively implicated in the ordering of a whole sequence of events. Although it is my contention that it is far too simplistic to equate disposal with waste per se, the issue of how we get rid of what is unwanted still has to be addressed because this is about as far as discussions of disposal have got. Not least because our present problem of definition stems from this treatment of the theme of disposal as `dirt' in the best-known writing in this area (notably Douglas, 1984 [1966]). How societies get rid of things and the role that this plays in creating social classifications, boundaries, and orders may have been of minor interest within sociology but it has for a long time been a theme of major significance within anthropology. Beginning with Henri Hubert and Marcel Mauss's work on sacrifice (1964 [1899]) and Mauss's analysis of the gift, especially his discussion of potlatch (1991 [1950]), we see that getting rid of something is profoundly implicated in the maintenance of a recognisable state of social order. The destructive waste of a life or of precious goods is seen as a conduit for the ongoing maintenance of social stability. The waste becomes a material expression of translation in the practices of ordering. In other words, even the most extreme destructive or violent acts against persons or things can have effects that make sense within the social order that members of that society understand. In this sense, disposal,

Secondhandedness: consumption, disposal and absent presence

161

expressed through its material forms, is part of the accomplishment of the ordering work that goes into making a society (see Bataille, 1991; Girard, 1977; 1989). The object as gift, the scapegoat, or sacrificial victim are all made as conduits of order through their disposability in a cycle of ongoing events. In engaging in such acts, members of a society can be seen to get rid of unwanted things and thereby to stabilise social categories of membership and belonging around their removal. In making something absent, either through death or destruction, a representation of social order is apparently secured but never for all time. Such acts often need to continue in an endless processual sequence in order to help reaffirm a sense of social order as a stable thing. It is noteworthy, too, that sacrifice as a form of disposal cannot be simply reduced to its final, violent conclusion. It has long been argued that there are a whole series of prior stages of preparation involved in the sacrificial act that have to be considered too as part of a sequence of disposal events (Hubert and Mauss, 1964). I would contend the same is true with disposal in nonsacrificial contexts as well although clearly a linear sequence would not always be the appropriate way to think about disposal in nonsacrificial contexts (see also Miller, 1998). In those few recent anthropological studies of disposal, it is this theme of how societies get rid of what is unwanted that has been prominent in discussion (Munro, 1992; 1995; Strathern, 1999). As Munro puts it, societies develop `conduits' for the disposal of unwanted images or meaning and not just for the objects of waste (1995). A precursor to these concerns is Douglas's analysis of dirt and pollution (1984 [1966]). Disposal, she argues, is all about questions of boundary and order it is about putting in place, beyond a certain threshold, all that threatens to pollute because it is seen as out of place. In her view, this is how classifications are made. Rubbish is made invisible by putting it beyond a certain threshold. Disposal in her account helps to affirm social categories, membership, and a sense of belonging for those who might be threatened by some unwarranted intrusion on their society from the representational `outside'. I say representational `outside' because it may not in fact be some foreign thing or person that is disposed of. That thing or person may be insidepart of the communitybut be seen as outside of the classificatory order of things. Disposal, for Douglas, involves the issue of something or someone going away so that classifications can be maintained. Dirt, for Douglas, is above all a spatial category. For Douglas, what is disposed of is pollution or dirt, famously defined as ``matter out of place'' (1984, page 35). The anomalous and the incongruous are a source of the figural `out-of-placeness' of this state of pollution that continues to present itself unless it is represented out of existence. Dirt appears where boundaries have not been performed correctly (or in ritual forms of transgression). Things, Douglas suggests, following Jean-Paul Sartre, can become sticky or viscous (page 38). The viscous defies the rules of classification. It unsettles because it is anomalous. It is neither a solid nor a liquid. As such, it has to be disposed of so that orderly classification can be maintained. It is represented out of existence through the known social rules of interpretation, or though physical control, avoidance, or by using it in such a way so as to remove its unsettling qualities through a transference onto something else, something better subject to the process of control (1984, pages 39 ^ 40). Dirt is, Douglas argues, approached through the question of order (1984, page 40). The drawing of boundaries, the creation of taboo, ritual forms of controlling an invoked anomaly, labeling, scapegoating, these are all examples of the representational ordering work that is undertaken to dispose of matter out of place (see also Girard, 1979). In her work, a sense of social order is seen to rest on such representational cleansing acts. Such an approach makes a clear distinction between the present and the absent, which is entirely intuitive to our understanding of what we can see and know.

162

K Hetherington

However, it is this intuitive sense of presence and absence that is problematic and raises questions about the character of her (structuralist) argument. No one would deny that societies become good at such forms of disposal. But nothing is ever perfect. The viscous has a tendency to remain tacky it does not always disappear completely in fact, it continues to tack. It has a motility as well as a mobilityit moves between a status of presence and absence and is transformed by so doing (Munro, 1997), seemingly disappearing only to return again unexpectedly and perhaps in a different place or in a different form. It can come and go, appear and disappear, and in so doing it remains unfinished and not fully disposed of no matter how much representational work we might do to put it somewhere where it is no longer perceived as out of place. It has a tendency to stick, even if only as a trace of what has passed. It is this movement between the categories of presence and absence that is key to understanding the role of disposal within consumption and it is precisely that which is missing when disposal is treated solely as an issue of dirt within the structuralist machine of classification and order rather than approached through a more fluid understanding of ordering processes (see Hetherington and Lee, 2000; Law, 1994). Douglas's approach too readily treats disposal as about making something absent for all time. But the absent is only ever moved along and is never fully gotten rid of. Its capacity for translation remains as an absence just as much as when a presence is encountered. Furthermore, rather than see this moving along as a problem we should acknowledge that it can also be a socially useful resource. Matter out of place in Douglas's account draws our attention to the spatiality of disorder and the subsequent ordering acts that aim to correct disorder. In her account, making something safe or disposing of it involves putting it there so that it is no longer here. `Put your rubbish in the bin.' `Take your dirty hands off the food.' `Bury your dead in the graveyard.' All of these invocations to order matter out of place through disposal involve a spatial displacement within an already-known regime of representational possibility. Of course, this binarism of the `here and there', Douglas herself would acknowledge, is too simple to account for all acts of disposal. She recognises that there is often a third space involved, the threshold itselfliminal, betwixt and between, itself uncertain and anomalouswhich is sometimes mobilised within this process (see also Turner, 1969; Van Gennep, 1960). Providing that this space is knowable and representable in advance and its location definite, this is not usually seen as a problem. Indeed, the neutralisation of the anomalous, the classificatory in-between and sticky state, is often seen as best dealt with through the ritualised transference (rites de passage) of disorder from the state itself to this in-between space that can be ordered and controlled through symbolic means (Turner, 1969). The problem with this analysis is that pollution never fully goes away in the manner that Douglas or Victor Turner tend to assume. They have a little too much faith in the powers of representation. As Marilyn Strathern more recently suggests in contrast, ``Pollution surprises by its untoward nature, an unlooked for return; yet those involved in the activity of waste disposal know that one cannot dispose of waste, only convert it into something else within its own life'' (1999, page 61). It is not just that it can be sticky but also that it can flow. Although Douglas does acknowledge that `dirt' can be a flexible resource, recursively involved in the making of a sense of order, she tends to focus on this issue through an understanding of previously established rules and conventions of representation within society. But dirt has nonrepresentational qualities that are intrinsic to it too. It is that which is missing in her account. It can be manifest as a figural absence as well as a discursive (and thereby representational) presence and can help to disorder in

Secondhandedness: consumption, disposal and absent presence

163

ways that provide a necessary flexibility to ordering processes (see Lyotard, 1984; Serres, 1991). It is largely because Douglas wants to see the category of social order as a stable and representable thing in advance of her analysis of how it is established and maintained in specific social orders that she misses the ongoing way in which order is made as uncertain process. `Dirt' has to do with the making and unmaking of that process rather than with a thing in itself. The disposal of absence Having `disposed' of Douglas in the previous section, the logic of my argument suggests that she has to remain in some form thereafter. Her contribution to the study of consumption has been to acknowledge its significance to questions of belonging and the rules of membership within society and I would not want to do away with that (Douglas and Isherwood, 1980). Neither would Munro, who, in a series of recent papers, has begun to open up our understanding of this theme of disposal and its ultimate impossibility (1992; 1995; 1998). Acknowledging, too, a debt to Douglas, his central concern is to suggest that consumption be seen as a performance of membership and communication through goods, rather than as a series of utilitarian, individual (rational) choices beloved of economists (see Douglas and Isherwood, 1980). Through this, he suggests, we have to address and find ways of controlling the proliferation of understandings or `meanings' that consumption generates. Looking at two different contexts, how disposal is an integral part of the food consumption process (1995) and how accountants make use of `X-gaps' (or blank figures) in their accounts (1998), Munro suggests that dirt, what we can call more abstractly an absent presence, can never be fully disposed of. What we do as food consumers will not simply depend on the choices we make in deciding what to eat or not eat but also on an acknowledgement in advance of the ``conduits for disposal'' (1995, page 313) that are available to us, in which we can dispose of the meaning of the food we consume. We put things in a supposedly stable context dispose of themso that we do not have to deal with their implications in a direct way. We do not just produce such implications when we acquire goods, we also dispose of them by keeping certain things outside. To that extent, Munro would agree with Douglas and Isherwood (1980). However, he recognises that the conduits of disposal (he cites the fridge as an example) do not always work effectively in managing such representations. The lingering smell of yesterday's fish in the fridge, even after we have eaten it, has the ability to remain (Munro, 1995, page 318). Such issues of disposal are not just physical though but also representational; they involve questions of how societies deal with ``the haunting presence of exclusion'' that is an inevitable part of consumer activities (1998, page 148). An implication of this analysis is that the disposal outcome is not one of rubbishing but of placing; this suggests we cannot get rid of the consequences of our actions but are held accountable as they translate our actions into other forms that are `out of control'. Disposal is a means, therefore, of managing our accountability and our debt to such effects. This is not just a matter of the lingering smell of fish or yesterday's washing up still `calling us' from the kitchen. It is also, significantly, a matter of epistemology; in particular, it is a question of how we account for or are held accountable by that which we have tried to dispose of but have left unfinished. Disposal in this approach becomes a question of `creative accounting' and of the way in which we use or deal with gaps the aporial absent presence with the unfinished disposal within our otherwise seamless representations:

164

K Hetherington

``Gaps in our knowledge, whatever else they are, are also places in which the unspeakability of the Other can reenter. Where gaps are closed through exclusion, they are also fissures through which the Other can leak back in'' (Munro, 1998, page 145). Munro recognises that representational stability, associated with acts of disposal, is never ultimately achieved as a form of closure in the way that Douglas wants to assume. As `accountants' we will always find recurring X-gaps in our daily lives. The question is how we respond to those gaps. All the same, Munro's analysis, although it hints at morewhat he calls a positive view of disposal (1992; 1998, page 149)is still mostly concerned with the idea of disposal as the `problem' of waste. Although that Other we call waste can indeed become a spectral horror, it can also be a resource. If we have to speak about rubbish at all in the context of disposal it should be in that more neutral manner. The idea that societies develop conduits of disposal that are themselves fluid and uncertain is a useful one. The problem though is that, in thinking about receptacles like rubbish bins and fridges as fluid conduits, metaphorically speaking they have a tendency to become something more akin to unfluid black holes when disposal gets reduced to an issue of waste. Rather than see the rubbish bin as the archetypal conduit of disposal I suggest the door is a better example. Not only do doors allow traffic in both directions when open, but also they can be closed to keep things outside/inside, present/absent, at least temporarily and provisionally. Figuratively, the door better captures the role of disposal within consumption. We can see this when we imagine that rubbish itself can be a conduit of disposal rather that which is placed in the conduit. This argument can be developed out of reading Thompson's analysis of the recursivity of rubbish (1979). Although Thompson does not discuss the issue of disposal directly, much of his analysis is taken up with addressing the role of rubbish within rather than at the end of the processes of consumption and with the disposal of value, in particular, that is attendant upon it. For Thompson, there are three classes of object that we might consume, each of which has a different status in relation to the issue of value: durable, transient, and rubbish objects. A durable object is one that has high status and value and is recognised socially as worthy or important he cites the example of a piece of antique Queen Anne furniture. A transient object, in contrast, is something that loses its status and value over timecars are the example cited in this case. Both sets of objects, Thompson argues, occupy what he calls regions of fixed assumptions (1979, page 8). In other words, in such a region an object is known, its status and value established, and we know how to respond to it accordingly. Social agents find ways of controlling these regions, they do ordering and representational work to establish and maintain them, especially in maintaining a separation between the categories of durability and transientness. No one who has a fine piece of 18th-century furniture wants it to be seen as transient, just as everyone would like their rusting old car to be seen as a `classic' (except, of course, those who already own what is deemed to be a classic car). If we relate this to Douglas's argument, the transient category, from the standpoint of the durable, would be seen as dirt that had to be kept from polluting that high-status category. Yet, the virtue of Thompson's analysis is that it does not rest on this binarism of separate and distinct regions of fixed assumption alone. There is in his analysis a third category, rubbish, which he suggests is more covert in nature and quite different from the transient, occupying what he calls a region of flexibility (1979, page 8). Here objects have little or no status or value at all, they become blanks that can address not only the question of value in the singular instance but also value as a general category. This is the space where transient objects end up. But they do not always remain there.

Secondhandedness: consumption, disposal and absent presence

165

Although all this talk of regions might appear today in all our concern with networks and other topologies as a little static and rigid in its structuralist assumptions (Mol and Law, 1994), Thompson hints at a more fluid analysis. But what is most interesting about Thompson's approach is the way that he considers the dynamic role of rubbish in relation to the two other categorieschallenging our intuitive understanding of rubbish as an end point in a sequence of the declining value of an object. He sees rubbish occupying a blank and fluid space between the other two categories, helping to maintain their separateness while also providing a conduit for objects to move back and forth into the regions of fixed assumptions. At one and the same time rubbish affirms the stasis of the order of value while also allowing for movement, flexibility, and change (see also Hetherington and Lee, 2000). In this sense rubbish is itself a conduit of disposala conduit of the disposal of value but it acts more like a door than a rubbish bin. Thompson illustrates this with two examples: Stevengraphs (late Victorian machinewoven silk pictures) and Regency housing in Islington, London, during the 1960s (see Thompson, 1979). Both were at one time popular artefacts that became transient before being seen as rubbish: uncollectable Victorian kitsch in one case, and run-down slum housing fit only for demolition in the other. Yet both have ended up subsequently back in the durable category. Thompson charts how a few collectors in the first instance and 1960s pioneer gentrifiers, the `knockers-through', in the second, were willing to accept the blank facility of rubbish and to champion its significance beyond its then current categorisation as nonrepresentational except as rubbishhereby making it visible and subsequently popular to others of a similar mind. Both are now expensive and highly sought after artefacts firmly established as durable objects. What this also shows, incidentally, is that collectors are just as much animated by the work they can do in establishing the reputation of a class of objects as they are by issues of rarity, classification, or possession. s of Sunday morning car-boot sales would attest, there is a As the many habitue tacit understanding of this dynamic of the blank by the many who are out looking for an overlooked bargain or a class of object whose day has yet to come (even Queen Anne furniture was once hopelessly unfashionable and rather cheap to buy). People know that some things are just tat, and others are design classics waiting to be discovered, sorted, and made durable in their respectability and value again. Yet today, more than when Thompson was writing in the late 1970s, even the outright tat often has its fans. Still, much collecting derives its meaning precisely from this dynamicthe making of the reputation of an object (and thereby its status and value) by making it visible, recognisable, and `respectable' (including cult or subcultural respectability with respect to kitsch). A cheap contemporary utilitarian object can be disposed of by one generation only to return later and be claimed as a design classic by the next. Not only are conduits of disposal implicated in changes of value of particular materials but also the fluidity of such conduits is implicated in the establishment of social relations like those associated with stability, provenance, and trustworthiness. And some conduits are better at this than others because they are more readily implicated in established relations of trust. The car-boot sale is an untrustworthy conduitit is `dodgy'. A much better conduit of disposal is the familya conduit through which the Queen Anne table can be `passed down'. But it is a conduit with fluid or door-like qualities. The table can also be held back if one's offspring prove to be a disappointment, sold off to pay for necessary renovation work on the chimney stack, moved on as part of a divorce settlement, be given to a museum in order to be offset against tax or death duties, or go down another line of the family if there are no children.

166

K Hetherington

Thompson goes on to discuss the further complexities of the dynamics of this threefold classification of objects (drawing on the mathematics of catastrophe theory). However, the point he makes most clearly is to acknowledge the recursive way in which `rubbish'that which has supposedly been disposed of is implicated in the relations between objects, in their relative status, and in their value. What his analysis shows is not only that societies have conduits of disposal for `dirt' (pace Munro) but that `dirt' is itself a conduit for the disposal of a certain kind of representation (value) and that it feeds that back into the other categories from whence it has come in a transformed state. Disposal as a fluid translating practice is implicated in the ordering processes associated with such representational stability. What it shows, though, is that change and transformation are a part of that processindeed, that one cannot always predict in advance what will remain in the category of dirt and what will return highly valued. Where Thompson's analysis is particularly limited, though, is in the fact that he only really extends his discussion of rubbish to its role in the establishment of mobility and flow within the field of exchange value. The whole issue of how a piece of rubbish might be valued in other ways or how one form of value might be translated into another is not really developed in his argument. A worthless item may still be practically useful, it may convey fond memories to its user, may be the conduit for sentiment, or may connect a person to loved ones or to their own past. Indeed, the whole arena of sentimental value as opposed to use, exchange, or sign value remains to be investigated sociologically and its potentially highly significant implications for consumption practices explored. Certainly it is highly significant for the practices of disposal as a form of placing. One of the reasons why people often do not get rid of things in a rational way when they have become practically useless or economically valueless is because they retain a high level of sentimental value. If we are, then, to understand fully the significance of disposal in relation to consumption practices we need to disassociate it from the class of objects we call rubbish or dirt and to open up our understanding of what is meant by value. Certainly, disposal can be about binning something, but it can also be about forgetfulness (sometimes deliberate); it can even be about maintaining something in such a state of abeyance so that it does not become rubbish, not only in the home but in the institutions of public culture, too. The museum is above all a conduit of disposal. Many museums have vast quantities of objects in store, which have been collected over the years but that never see a display case. They become part of the reserve army of objects (or perhaps a study collection) and are usually seen only by curatorial staff or specialists in a particular field, if at all. They are disposed of in the sense that they are put away out of sight from a viewing public. That creates its own problemsnotably the need for storage space, which may often be in short supply. Objects have a tendency to leak out of cupboards. But even when an object is put out of view and is not readily accessible it can still have effects through other media: in the card index or catalogue those items may be just as visible as items on display. The fact that they are in store at all attests to the fact that the museum does not want to get rid of them, it wants to keep them for posterity because they are seen as either important in themselves or representative of a class of object. There are few things that institutions like museums and libraries agonise over more than disposal in the sense of deaccessioning. Whether socially this is a form of sentiment is an open question. In effect, these objects are disposed of into a place that holds them in abeyance in order to prevent them being lost forever beyond the walls of the museum. Similarly in the home it is not just the bin that is the conduit for disposal. The attic, the basement, the garage, fridge, wardrobe, make-up drawer, or cupboard under

Secondhandedness: consumption, disposal and absent presence

167

the stairs, even the public rooms of the house itself, are all often used in the same manner as conduits for disposing of things which are forgotten, sometimes until they are tidied away or thrown out, sometimes for a whole lifetime, until the houseclearance people come along after a death in the family. But what are not disposed of are the translating effects of those objects. Old photographs or family heirlooms might retain a presence in the attic just as powerfully as when they are brought down from the attic to be reappropriated perhaps by subsequent generations concerned with family history. Even their memory after they have gone from the house can still have effects. Disposal and inheritance are not as far apart as might initially be imagined. These receptacles act more like doorways than trashcans. This is more than a question of storage though. Storage implies some kind of intention to hold something provisionally as absent and to avoid any translating effects that it might perform. But not all disposal is intentional and nor is its return. The semiotic mutability of that which has been disposed of can return in a manner different from when it was disposed. Former minor connotations associated with an object might come to take on a denotative character. The locations of something made absent may change its character, whether that be in allowing it to attain an attractive antique patina or in just allowing it to go moldy in a bag at the back of a cupboard. Likewise, things not intentionally disposed of can get lost. In other words, in the dynamics of consuming in which disposal is an integral part, the absent can assume agentic powers independent from any human intentionalityindeed, whole scientific disciplines such as archaeology are (tacitly) founded on just such a principle. Make a visit to any cheap antique centre on a Sunday afternoon and listen to the comments of other shoppers. People go there not only to buy but also to reminisce with the objects that they see on display (as well as with accompanying friends and family): `They've got my tea pot!', `I used to have one of those', `Your dad broke one of those soon after we got married!' The importance an object may hold for someone can be conveyed by its absence in one place just as much as by its presence in another. Sometimes the absence of an object (brought to recollection by a similar one on view) can be so strong that people still think they have things long after they have got rid of them. As consumers, people do membership and identity work not only through what they acquire, as most of the more sociological literature on consumption now suggests (following Douglas and Isherwood, 1980; see also Hebdige, 1979; 1988; Lury, 1996), but also through what they dispose of and how they dispose of consumed objects. An old wedding dress still in its box in the loft, the pair of candelabras split up after a death with one going to the son another to the daughter, the chipped vase kept for sentimental reasons: disposal sometimes involves making things, or the people associated with them, not just physically absent but representationally present at the same time. Likewise, an effect is that sometimes this action of making things representationally absent can also make them nonrepresentationally present. Think of the objects on view in a display case either at home or in a museum. Is their placement there on display, sometimes for years in the same arrangement, not itself a form of disposal by making something representationally absent? The fact that it is has been made apparent in recent years in a number of museums in Britain, including national museums, that have allowed artists to make `interventions' within those display cases. This has usually taken the form of putting anomalous objects into ordered displaysplaster casts of discarded pairs of knickers (so-called `knicker beasts') in fossil cabinets in the Pitt Rivers museum in one recent example or putting contemporary artworks in alongside old objects, often because they have been a source of inspiration for a contemporary artist. What these objects attain (and it is their

168

K Hetherington

purpose in the former case, the latter is more subtle in its effects) is to reveal precisely that permanent display cabinets are spaces of disposal brought to life again by the shock effect of an incongruous, nonrepresentational blank that unsettles either a class of objects, a classificatory scheme, or a visual sense of representational order. We are made to see not only the knicker beasts but also the fossils that have been disposed of in their display since they were collected perhaps over a hundred years earlier at a time when the theory of evolution was still novel and shocking and more people were interested in fossils than they are today. Consumers of all kinds engage in acts of disposal with things that they have. But the erasure of an object is never complete. There is always a trace effect that is passed on by its absence. Whether it be an avid collector who disposes of his or her collection into the indexing work that he or she does, a tourist who disposes of his or her holiday into holiday photographs, or someone who buys a set of six cast-iron pans but only regularly uses two of them, disposing of the others in the back of the cupboard, all of these acts can be seen as acts of disposal that are far removed from any simple association with rubbishing. The question is not specifically about how an object gets placed but about what happens to the ordering effects of that object within that placing. All acts of arrangement and ordering involve moving representations about in order to stabilise them but that sense of order and stillness is rarely achieved in practice. Think of the look of horror on the face of a lifelong collector of Chantilly porcelain when he or she finds, after reading a piece in the newspaper on recent archaeological research, that one of his or her major pieces bought some years ago at great expense was actually made at St Cloud. Above all, then, disposal is about the mobilisation of absence (blanks) in the making of ordering processes through placing activity that engages with the categories of presence and absence. Indeed, getting into the terrain of definitions, we might go a little further and say that disposal is about the mobilisation, ordering, and arrangement of the agency of the absent. Perhaps the most useful account we have of such management comes not from the study of consumption but from the disposal of the dead in Hertz's famous account of the practices of first and second burial within funeral rites (1960). Disposal and the second Through a comparative study of funeral rites, Hertz was able to show the two-stage nature that those rites take in many cultures. Once a person has died his or her family or community becomes responsible not only for the disposal of his or her bodily remains but also for his or her soul. The act of disposal often involves an initial and provisional `burial' which may last anything from a few days to a number of years depending on the particular culture in question. After that burial the remains are still available to the community. Subsequently a second and more final burial will take place where the remains of the person will be finally disposed of and will assume a form of closure once the person's soul is assumed to have passed on, often into the company of other souls. It is what happens in the gap between these two burials that is of particular interest for Hertz and for us in considering the fluid composition of disposal. In part, this gap is a space for preparing the soul for its final place of rest and, in part, it involves the living honouring a debt they feel they have to the departed. The ritual is, of course, in part about ordering and controlling possible sources of pollution and the unmanaged return of unsettled and malign spirits (pace Douglas) but it is also about the use that is made of absence within presence. The gap between first and second burial has both a temporal and a spatial dimension: interval in the first instance and segregation in the second. Disposal is an act of double take. Disposal of the body allows preparation for the soul before the final disposal of the body allows the soul to move on. The body is

Secondhandedness: consumption, disposal and absent presence

169

disposed of and then brought back before being finally disposed of. The gapthe time ^ space between the two funeralsis concerned with the motility of presence and absence and their enfolded state in a seemingly valueless or valuable set of material remains. It is a space of abeyance in which living persons (re)construct their identities through an extension of themselves beyond their own bodies in the realm of these material bodily remains (on extension see Strathern, 1991). Remains are put at a distance representationally while remaining close physically in first burial and then brought back as representationally close but physically distant after second burial. Through such rites of the double take a debt is honoured, the person and the soul of the departed reaches a settled state, and the person doing the honouring establishes a sense of who they are through a closure to the act of disposing. In particular, such a rite constitutes the practice of disposal as one of membership and identity through what might be described as an ethics of care (see Harbers et al, 2002). How one translates these arguments about the double-take into the disposal of inanimate articles one has shopped for, rather than kin one has been born into the midst of, remains to be answered. In some cultures the distance between disposing of people and things is not all that distant at all. In Japan, for instance, holding funeral rites for inanimate objects is a common practice (see Kretschmer, 2000). Mortuary rites kuyo are performed for everyday objects when they cease to be useful either because they are worn out or broken. Different objects have different shrines where they are disposed of. Needles, for example, when worn out, are often taken by their users to a needle shrine to be disposed of. First burial, in this context, involves them being inserted into a block of tofu. A prayer of thanksgiving for their useful life is then said over them. Later the priest who cares for the shrine will take all the needles away and dispose of them a second time after a second prayer (see Kretschmer, 2000). And it is not just traditional work tools that are disposed of in this way. Consumables like spectacles have had shrines for a centuries. But even new classes of objects have shrines too. For example, there are now shrines in Japan for worn-out computer motherboards (and probably for mobile phones also). What is being disposed of is not only the item but also its value. It is the separation of the value from the item that requires the state of preparation between first and second burial. Value is the equivalent of a soul for an object. In the West, this practice is less clearly visible as religious ritual but it is present nonetheless. Conduits of disposal often have this two-stage `holding' process through which consumer objects pass before becoming waste. The bookcase, the recycle bin on a computer, the garage, the potting shed, the fridge, the wardrobe, even the bin, are often constituted more as sites of first burial rather than of second burial. Items are held in them for a period of time while their uncertain value state is addressed (use, exchange, or sentimental value) before being removed into the representational outside where they undergo their second burial in the incinerator, the landfill, or unfortunately sometimes just fly-tipped onto the side of the road. The object itself is disposed of though such second burial because its value and how that is translated and then moved on has to be addressed first. This is something that first burial alone cannot do. If the intrinsic worth of a person is assumed to be their soul, the intrinsic worth of an artefact is its valueuse value and sentimental value as much as exchange or sign value. Only when all forms of value have been exhausted or translated and thereby stabilised will the object be permitted to undergo its second burial. But although we might rely on the principles of first and second burial when disposing of a consumable we cannot be quite so clear whether second burial has actually taken place: a broken pot thrown into the ditch in the 3rd century may turn out to be extremely valuable as dating evidence for archaeologists 1700 years later and may find its way into a museum or even an antiques shop thereafter. The object,

170

K Hetherington

then, may be reprieved or resurrected, in the manner that Thompson describes (1979), or it may disappear absolutely. There are clearly cultural differences between disposing of a person and disposing of an inanimate thing but abstractly the use of a gap between a first and second action, where presence and absence are enfolded into the question of value between two acts in which that thing is put away, remains apparent in both cases. The gap is the space where things are held in a state denying their wastagewhere they are held at our disposal for a second time so that we can attain a settlement with their remaining value. Such a settlement is often about identity. We are not just `what we buy' but also `what we do not throw out'at least not until a respectable interval has passed for any residual value to be passed onand also `what we value'. And it is in that space that we find a concern with matters of care (or their lack) and begin to see how consumption is not so much a utilitarian and selfish act of pleasuring ones desires as a communitarian source of social integration, identity making, and membership-confirming activity. Disposal and settlement: issues of secondhandedness Most of the time such acts of disposal are a routine and ordinary part of consumption practice. It is about how we manage absencehow we order it, where we place it, when we use it as a source of value, and so on. As long as we do not encounter that absence as unexpected presence, in effect an unresolved question of value, the conduits of disposal can be said to be working effectively. The utility of absence is as much a part of the communicative and ordering activity associated with consumption as it is a part of the acquisition and use of some object or service as a mark of social membership. We see this perhaps a little more obviously in the practices associated with `important' examples of disposal such as in the disposal of a house onto the market, the disposal of a kitten or puppy, or the disposal of the effects of a loved one who has just died. People will often say that they want such `artefacts' to `go to a good home'. Why? Because they have valued it and expect that valuing to continue. But to appreciate fully the agency of absence we see most clearly the importance, recursivity, and ongoing nature of disposal when the management of absence does not work effectively, when it unexpectedly returns or attains a presence and shocks us into a recognition of its significance. We see this most clearly when the expected processes associated with disposal are unfinished or are carried out in an ineffective manner and where questions of value are not properly honoured. The representational figure of unfinished or unmanaged disposal is the ghost and its agency is expressed in the idea of haunting (see Gordon, 1997). This is where the act of second burial has failed, been hurried, or has not been carried out to its full effect. We encounter the unexpected presence of absence as a ghost. In consumption practices there are many ghosts. Things we threw out before we should, things we held onto long after they should have been disposed of, the credit-card statement at the end of the month, or the absence marked with a little red `o/d' next to a figure in the bank balance, are some of the most obvious examples that people routinely encounter as a consequence of their consumer activities. Ghosts do not only moan and rattle their chains they also speak the language of credit and debt. In a word they are the figure of value untranslated. Commonly, we understand haunting as an unacknowledged debt and feel a sense of guilt in its presence. It is a debt that we, heirs to past consumption, owe for the failure to dispose of something in the proper manner (see Derrida, 1994). It is a debt that has to be settled. Future generations expect their inheritance and themselves reciprocate through the sense of debt and obligation they owe to their ancestors.

Secondhandedness: consumption, disposal and absent presence

171

Disposal, then, within consumer activity is about managing an ever-present potential absence such that that absence does not itself make an appearance as a visible agent. For its agency to be dealt with effectively requires successful doorkeeping. All the while it can be moved alongdisposed ofit remains unseen as an absence and the conduits of disposal within the consumption process can be said to be working effectively. This implies more than trying to avoid spending too much and getting into financial debt. It also means managing a whole array of social relations through consumption in such a way that we affirm our membership of society effectively. It is not just the act of consuming that positions us in this way as Mary Douglas and Baron Isherwood have argued (1980), disposal, too, is an integral part of that process. In the most mundane way, then, we encounter unfinished disposal through the idea of an unpaid debt. We encounter it in the credit-card bill that arrives after a spending spree; after the expensive new outfit has been worn and lost its glamour. We encounter it also in the detritus that consumption leaves behind waiting to be dealt with, whether that be crumbs on the floor after a quick snack or vast areas of tropical rainforest remaindered as tree stumps in our demand for veneered luxury. But as a social practice, rather than an individual one, debt and the need to honour it in order to avoid being haunted are part of the way in which consumer membership is performed. Pots and pans may not literally start flying around the room if this is not done but representational instability will occur when the conduits for disposal do not operate effectively. Disposal that is completed in two stages serves to help stabilise, materially, social relations within the consumption process and the transformation of value from one form to another that is central to that process. Such activity is part of the membership work that constitutes the terrain of consumption, the figure of the ghost arrives where we fail to honour that commitment or when we do it unsuccessfully or halfheartedly. Haunting, then, connotes debt but not only in the language of credit cards. It also suggests the importance of disposal to an ethics of how we `consume' each other as responsible social agents. By ethics I do not simply mean careful consumption, recycling old bottles and newspapers and so on, but how, through consumption, people relate to one another. This ethics is premised on a notion of the care for the absent, a making of the self through an encounter with its presence, and a concern for its possible return if the conduits through which it is moved are not managed effectively. Issues of social membership, recognition, order, acceptance, status, honour, self-worth are based not just on how one consumes but also on how one disposes. The social relations of consumption involve consumers not only as shoppers, gourmands, and car drivers but also as doorkeepers. To attend a door is a tactile or haptic encounter with the material world. Who has a hand on the door (or the market) matters. But within such consumer relations we cannot rely on the supposed hidden hand of the market to guide us, nor always on the visible (first) hand of the gift. Rather it is often our own second hand, a receiving as well as a giving hand, a hand that moves value on, that matters most. The handedness of the market, a consumer market in which disposal is a key part, is one of such translations as are constituted through the `passing on' of this capacity for secondhandedness. In the arena of consumption, second burial is perhaps better understood as secondhandedness. Not only do we dispose of things by passing them on but we manage the fluidity of the conduits of disposal through such handed activity just as much as we manage the things that pass through them. We attend on the door as a conduit of disposal in order to try and effect admittance or nonadmittance and in which direction. Failure to do this effectively can mean more than feeling spooked, it carries risks with it as the ongoing cases of unmanaged disposal in consumption associated with global warming,

172

K Hetherington

the unapproved removal of organs from bodies in autopsies in British hospitals, and BSE all illustrate. The idea of unsettled spirits is an apposite one. Sociologically, disposal as a consumption practice is all about settlementa settlement that takes place as something or someone comes in or goes out through the door. Settlement connotes several things. Most obviously it connotes a legal, contractual agreement as in terms like `divorce settlement' or `out-of-court settlement'; it also connotes a coming to rest through movement as in `the house settled after it was constructed'. If settlement connotes such things it also denotes the way in which disposal is integrated within the process of consumption. Consumption is about how we negotiate the settlement of social relations; it involves our tacit acknowledgment of the ways in which we make things absent in order to establish that settlement. Settlement may imply the mundane activity of putting the children's toys away in the attic after they have grown up and left home, but we use consumption as a means of disposal more generally in order to come to a settlement with how we manage our relations with others in terms of our memories, a sense of tradition, and through our relations not only with our contemporaries but also with our ancestors and future generations. Disposal as a theme is important not just because it is a stage of consumption which has been left out of most of the sociological writing but because it is involved in making consumption as a social and ethical activity make sense as such.
Acknowledgements. I am grateful to Rolland Munro, Sharon Macdonald, and Tony Waters for

their comments and suggestions of reading in connection with this paper.

References Adorno T, Horkheimer M, 1979 Dialectic of Enlightenment (New Left Books, London); first published in 1944 Bataille G, 1991 The Accursed Share volume 1 (Zone Books, New York); first published in 1967 Baudrillard J, 1996 The System of Objects (Verso, London); first published in 1968 Baudrillard J, 1998 The Consumer Society (Sage, London); first published in 1970 Bowlby R, 1985 Just Looking (Methuen, New York) Bowlby R, 2000 Carried Away (Faber and Faber, London) Brown P, 1981 The Cult of the Saints (University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL) Callon M, 1986, ``Some elements of a sociology of translation: domestication of the scallops and the fishermen of St Brieuc Bay'', in Power, Action and Belief Ed. J Law (Routledge and Kegan Paul, London) pp 196 ^ 233 Chappells H, Shove E, 1999, ``The dustbin: a study of domestic waste, household practices and utility services'' International Planning Studies 4 267 ^ 280 Clark A, 1999 Tupperware (Smithsonian Institute Press, Washington, DC) Dant T, 2000 Material Culture in the Social World (Open University Press, Buckingham) Debord G, 1977 Society of the Spectacle (Black and Red, Detroit, MI); first published in 1967 Derrida J, 1994 Spectres of Marx (Routledge, New York) Douglas M, 1984 Purity and Danger (Ark, London); first published in 1966 Douglas M, Isherwood B, 1980 The World of Goods (Routledge and Kegan Paul, London) Featherstone M, 1991 Consumer Culture and Postmodernism (Sage, London) Gabriel Y, Lang T, 1995 The Unmanageable Consumer (Sage, London) Girard R, 1977 Violence and the Sacred (Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD) Girard R, 1989 The Scapegoat (Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD) Gordon A, 1997 Ghostly Matters (University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, MN) Gregson N, 1993, ``And now its all consumption'' Progress in Human Geography 19 135 ^ 141 Gregson N, 1997, ``Performance and possession: rethinking the act of purchase in the light of the car boot sale'' Journal of Material Culture 2 241 ^ 263 Gregson N, Crewe L, Brooks K, 2002,``Shopping, space, and practice'' Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 20 597 ^ 617 Harbers H, Mol A-M, Stollmeyer A, 2002, ``Food matters: arguments for an ehtnography of daily care'' Theory, Culture and Society 19(5/6) 207 ^ 226

Secondhandedness: consumption, disposal and absent presence

173

Haug W, 1986 Critique of Commodity Aesthetics (Polity Press, Cambridge); first published in 1971 Hawkins G, 2000, ``Plastic bags: living with rubbish'' International Journal of Cultural Studies 4 5 ^ 23 Hebdige D, 1979 Subculture (Routledge, London) Hebdige D, 1988 Hiding in the Light (Routledge, London) Hertz R, 1960, ``A contribution to the study of the collective representation of death'', in Death and the Right Hand translated by R Needham, C Needham (Cohen and West, London) pp 27 ^ 86; first published in 1907 Hetherington K, Lee N, 2000, ``Social order and the blank figure'' Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 18 169 ^ 184 Hubert H, Mauss M, 1964 Sacrifice (Cohen and West, London); first published in 1899 Kretschmer A, 2000, ``Mortuary rites for inanimate objects: the case of Hari Kuyo '' Japanese Journal of Religious Studies 27 379 ^ 404 Latour B, 1993 We Have Never Been Modern (Harvester Wheatsheaf, Hemel Hempstead, Herts) Latour B, 2002, ``Morality and technology: the end to means'' Theory, Culture and Society 19(5/6) 247 ^ 260 Law J, 1994 Organising Modernity (Blackwell, Oxford) Lefebvre H, 1971 Everyday Life in the Modern World (Allen Lane, London) Lury C, 1996 Consumer Culture (Polity Press, Cambridge) Lyotard J-F, 1984 Driftworks (Semiotext(e), New York) Marcuse H, 1968 One Dimensional Man (Sphere, London) Marx K, 1938 Capital volume 1 (George Allen and Unwin, London); first published in 1867 Marx K, 1973 Grundrisse (Penguin, Harmondsworth, Middx); first published in 1939 Mauss M, 1991 The Gift (Routledge, London); first published in 1950 Miller D, 1987 Material Culture and Mass Consumption (Blackwell, Oxford) Miller D (Ed.), 1995 Acknowledging Consumption (Routledge, London) Miller D, 1998 A Theory of Shopping (Polity Press, Cambridge) Mol A, Law J, 1994, ``Regions, networks and fluids: anaemia and social topology'' Social Studies of Science 24 641 ^ 671 Munro R, 1992, ``Disposal of the body: upending postmodernism'', mimeo, available at http://users.wbs.warwick.ac.uk/ephemera/ephemeraweb/journal/issues/1-2/1-2r-munro.pdf Munro R, 1995, ``The disposal of the meal'', in Food Choices Ed. D Marshall (Blackie Academic and Professional, London) Munro R, 1997, ``Ideas of difference: stability, social spaces and the labour of division'', in Ideas of Difference Eds K Hetherington, R Munro (Blackwell, Oxford) pp 3 ^ 26 Munro R, 1998, ``Disposal of the X gap: the production and consumption of accounting research and practical accounting systems'' Advances in Public Interest Accounting 7 139 ^ 159 Nava M, 1992 Changing Cultures (Sage, London) O'Brien M, 1999, ``Rubbish power: towards a sociology of the rubbish society'', in Consuming Cultures Eds J Hearn, S Roseneil (Macmillan, Basingstoke, Hants) pp 262 ^ 277 Pahl R, 1984 Divisions of Labour (Blackwell, Oxford) Sahlins M, 1972 Stone Age Economics (Aldine ^ Atherton, Chicago, IL) Serres M, 1991 Rome (Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA) Shields R, 1989, ``Social spatialisation and the built environment: the West Edmonton Mall'' Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 7 147 ^ 164 Shields R (Ed.), 1992 Lifestyle Shopping (Routledge, London) Slater D, 1997 Consumer Culture and Modernity (Polity Press, Cambridge) Strasser S, 2000 Waste and Want (Owl Books, New York) Strathern M, 1991 Partial Connections (Rowman and Littlefield, Savage, MD) Strathern M, 1999, ``The aesthetics of substance'', in Property, Substance and Effect (Athlone, London) pp 45 ^ 64 Thompson M, 1979 Rubbish Theory (Oxford University Press, Oxford) Thrift N, 2000, ``Afterwords'' Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 18 213 ^ 255 Titmuss R, 1970 Gift Relationships (George Allen and Unwin, London) Turner V, 1969 The Ritual Process (Routledge and Kegan Paul, London) Van Gennep A, 1960 The Rites of Passage (University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL) Veblen T, 1991 The Theory of the Leisure Class (Augustus Kelly, Fairfield, NJ); first published in 1899 Warde A, 1997 Consumption, Food and Taste (Sage, London) Williams R, 1982 Dream Worlds (University of California Press, Berkeley, CA)

2004 a Pion publication printed in Great Britain

También podría gustarte